The main concern of this paper is to attempt an assessment of one of the most brilliant and comprehensive syntheses, that advanced by Henri Van Lier in his book entitled "The New Age", 1962. It is a significant essay presenting an intellectually inspiring and invigorating integration of technology, science, art and ethics, viewed in the perspective of an all-embracing, philosophical vision of culture. It is one of the most symptomatic expressions of the quest for ideological and philosophical orientation to be found in contemporary Western thought. Further, it is a synthesis of a special kind, for it is worked out as if the march is simultaneously "in progress" and at the crossroads. Janusz Kuczynski. C. 1990
Published in : The International Society for Metaphysics. Studies in Methaphysics, volume I, Person and Nature.
* * *
INTRODUCTION
A. Omnipresence of technique
Indeed, we cannot doubt
that Homo – standing apart from all other beings through his angular and
angularising articulations and by his flat hands in bilateral symmetry –
should be a technician from instant to instant. In the phylogenesis, Homo
erectus developed techniques one million years before he practiced somewhat
detailed languages. In its ontogenesis, each hominoid specimen swims in a
technician environment from its cradle or the arms of his genitors. Our
languages only have significance insofar as they are the phonic or written thematisations
of a preliminary technical milieu. Although they have forgotten it, 'classic'
linguistics from Saussure to Chomsky very well described the formal properties
of languages, but were unable to understand that it matters. For Homo, even
'Nature' is made technical. Paths cross his forests. He ritually hunts or rears
his animals.
We have noted that angularising techniques prolong Homo's
angular body hence increasing its powers, sometimes disproportionately. Yet,
there is something more essential. Techniques introduce and support the own
spaces and times of each people, hence its topology, cybernetic,
logico-semiotic, its presentivity, what we call its culture or its
civilization. The absence of the wheel comforted the constrictive and
future-less cultures of Amerindians. At the oppostive, their constrictive and
future-less grasping dictated that they should not invent the wheel.
The technique is so much
the first and the last for Homo that he usually conceives the entire Universe
as a technical object to which he elects a master Technician: the Gods, a
unique demiurge, general fluxes, or still, a great Axiom. To such an extent
that we may ask ourselves whether the origin of many of Homo's metaphysic
problems does not lie in that he is incapable of conceiving anything but a
technical object, whereas the Universe, which produced him as a technician, is
not a technical object, but precisely a natural object. Creare, make grow, is the active tense of
crescere, growing. Technician Homo was quicker to understand creare than crescere.
B. Absence of theories of the technique
Since technique is so
important to Homo, we could have expected that it should trigger multiple and
rich philosophies. Such is not the case. Not Plato, not Plotinus, not Saint
Thomas Aquinas, not Descartes, not Kant, not Hegel, not even Marx elaborated
philosophies of the technique. There is nothing in Confucius or Lao-tze in
China, or in Çankara or Ramanuya in India. In the end, Aristotle is the only
one who, because he enjoyed seeing things from the bottom up, stopped before
'technical objects' at the same time as he stopped before 'animal parts' (De
partibus animalium).
And the result was the famous theory of the four causes: to technically produce
an object – for instance a Greek vase – we need an aim (final
cause), a matter (material
cause), a form (formal
cause), and a
producing agent (efficient cause). To these causes, the Medieval added the
instrumental cause (a potters' wheel, a chisel, and a hammer). In their vision,
we see that the final cause – which is the first and the last – is
the 'most noble', the one that justifies all others. It is that cause that
means that, for the Greek and the Romans, the Mediterranean Universe was a
Cosmos-Mundis (non-vile), of which Homo is the Microcosm.
With the planetary success
of western physics and techniques, the Aristotelian theory of the four causes
became the model for all causalities, human or divine. Jehovah himself shares
this model with the bartender, the surgeon, and the theologian. This Efficient
Cause created Adam by sculpting, in the matter (alluvium), a form whose final
cause was 'to his image and resemblance'.
C. First awakenings
In summary, we had to wait
until the 1930's and Mumford's 'Technique and civilization' before it was
stated that every civilization and culture were above and foremost a question
of technique. Hence, the invention of the 'chase' of the clockmaking wheels in the late Middle
Ages inaugurated relatively exact and constant timetables that allowed the West
to move from maritime coastal navigation to the crossing of oceans, then from
the Workshop to the Manufacture, to the Arsenal, the Factory, the Industry,
triggering simultaneously Convents and Nation States. Until the day Homo
discovered a 'being-of-the-temporal world', Heidegger's 1927 Dasein of Sein und Zeit.
It was only in 1957 that
Gilbert Simondon, a young French doctoral candidate, dared a decidedly
philosophical title: Du mode d'existence des objets techniques. Yes, indeed, technical objects had
a 'practical' but also an 'existential' scope. Until then, there had been
'Histories of the technique' and 'Museums of the technique', but they went no
further than juxtaposing descriptions and dating machines and processes.
Simondon's revolutionary work went largely unnoticed. Was it deemed too
technical for philosophers, and too philosophical for technicians? Or was it
simply too unsettling… Just think! Technical objects, the slaves of our daily
lives, would concern, condition, and carry the secret perception that we have of
our existences! Whereas existentialism had only just suggested that existing (sistere, ex, being projected towards) is the
ultimate framework of human destiny and freedom.
Yet, in 1959, the author of
the present Anthropogénie found the Du Mode d'existence des
objets techniques.
He had only just published Les Arts de l'Espace, where painting, sculpture, architecture, and
the fine arts were understood as being the produce of particular technical
gestures; gestures capable of constructing and maintaining the space-times of
groups or individuals like ordinary technical gestures, but also to thematize
these space-times, and even to grant them a statute of absolute (solvere, ab,
untying from any local and transitory operativity) by boosting or neutralizing
them. Since the work focused on the arts of space, the thematized and
absolutised space-times were called 'pictorial subject', 'sculptural subject',
or still, 'architectural subject', so many 'work subjects' that had a sense per
se, independently from the descriptive or narrative themes that they conveyed.
Among the work subjects, da Vinci's Mona Lisa, Michelangelo's David, Borromini's Chiesa were a 'Vinci', a 'Michelangelo', a
'Borromini' before being a Mona Lisa, a David or a Roman Chiesa. In Africa, the
statue of a king, an antelope or a monkey were, through the work subject,
'Kuba', or 'Luba', and 'Bambara' or 'Dogon' before being a king, an antelope or
a monkey… even though they were that too, politically and ritually.
During the sixties, Homo was decidedly moving from what the
Anthropogénie calls WORLD 2 – the world of
the 'distant continuous' of Greece and the West – to WORLD 3, the world
of contemporary 'discontinuous'. This violent turn was obviously caused by new
Sciences, new Arts, and new Ethics, but also and more initially by the mutation
of the Technique. Indeed, the latter was moving from 'energy machines' that had
ruled since the origins of Homo to 'information machines' whose theory had
begun being explained with the Theory of information and the 1948 Cybernetic.
This abrupt turn was dramatized by two world wars, inchoatively (inchoativement) in 1914-18 and decisively in
1940-45.
Thereby, Le Nouvel Age is the sum of the Les Arts de
l'espace and Du
mode d'existence des objets techniques. The three chapters of the present work on
science, art, and ethics were preceded by a chapter on technique that was as
considerable as the three former put together. In October 1963, Gilbert
Simondon, who was putting the finishing touches to L'individu et sa genèse physico-biologique, published in 1964, wrote the
following lines to the author (who chose the italics), which are enlightening
as to the three works: 'I admire the strength of the ideas, the richness of the
documentation, and this unity, this power of integration that makes your book the testimony
of a way of thinking that has its own logic, its own axiomatic capable of accounting for the modes
of realities that are just appearing through the process of technical inventions. Furthermore, this work possesses a
true aesthetic strength that is capable of creating a link, of instituting a communication
under a sort of activity of the imaginative oversimplicity'. In this context, the term
'aesthetic' assuredly meant a grasping of things that, in the space-times of
human productions – hence in their topology, cybernetic, logico-semiotic
and presentivity – perceives their existential implications and
instaurations, whether relating to daily objects, scientific theories, works of
art, political or religious protocols, traditions, etc.
Perhaps because of this
'generalised aesthetic' (the work of another author bore the same title at the
time) 1962's Nouvel Age had much more scope than the two works – albeit remarkable
– of Gilbert Simondon. Poland's Academy of sciences, which was then
trying to open soviet Marxism to modernity (and in particular to phenomenology)
hurriedly translated it into polish, Nowy Wiek, adding a preface that had socio-political
undertones, which the original did not have. In Canada, in 1962, the same year
as the Nouvel Age,
Mc Luhan strongly brought focus on the Technique through his genius shortcut:
'The medium is the message'. In the latter, he thrusts forward, in just five
words, that the technical structures of a media (radio, television, etc) were
in itself a message (existential) more fundamental than the particular messages
that it conveyed. Hence, he felt that he could make a distinction between 'hot'
media (radio) from 'cold' media (television). Prime Minister Trudeau heard of
the Nouvel Age
from Jean Lemoyne, his adviser. He decided to give the author all the necessary
means, including television teams, to organize an international seminar on the
theme 'Technique and its cultural implications'.
What interests us here is not that the author jumped at the
opportunity. Perhaps his penchant for a 'generalized aesthetic' already led him
towards 1965's L'Intention sexuelle', and to his
1970 reflections on Industrial design. What is
remarkable is that no one cared to take over a project for an international
seminar on Technique, which was ready. When in 1990, the Société internationale
de Métaphysique – regrouping forty or so countries – dedicated, in
its first volume Person and Nature, a long
chapter to Technique under the signature of Janusz Kuczynski, it almost
exclusively used the Nouvel Age as reference.
D. A few reasons behind this negligence
What is behind this
repression and even this foreclusion of technique in human ontologies and
epistemologies? The theme alone would deserve multiple doctorates. We shall
make do with a few ideas.
(a) When Homo, this living
bio-techno-semiotic, creates the first systems of his Cosmos-World, he goes
immediately to the signs, even to the most elevated signs: stars. He does this using a mixture of
astrology and astronomy that we encounter in Egypt and in Sumer, but also on
the other side of the world, with the Australian aboriginals. Then, he becomes
more rational during the 'axial period' (Jaspers), in the era around –
500, when he turns to more or less mathematical abstractions, such as Pythagorean figures,
Platonist figures, organic topologies of Aristotle's eternal species, mutual
conversions (Yi) of the Yin and the Yang, Quick (thick universal blood) of the
Amerindian, Good and Evil of Manichaeism. As if the sublime alone was capable of justifying
Homo. As though remarking on some of the techniques, too contingent or too
heavily material (guè-ôdès, said Plato), would have compromised its justification as a
culminating species.
(b) Homo has always attributed
properties of revelation, lucidity, and almost divine demonstration to his
languages. However, we humiliate this illusion if we recognize that language
relations ('in languages there are only differences' Saussure) are only the
specifications and thematisations of the technical relations that they are
satisfied with suspending (putting in between parentheses) the operating
dimension.
(c) Technique is not only a means, it is also a milieu. A milieu is largely independent
from what it encompasses; there are unforeseeable developments, it dominates
more than it serves. Recognizing the status of Technique's 'milieu' in human
reality means recognizing its modesty. We could think that, in order for this
humility to be bearable, we had to wait for the sixties when Homo started
realizing that the Evolution is in no way orthogenetic, but luxurious. That it
is not a constant growth towards him, as Spencer and Bergson thought around
1900 and Teilhardt de Chardin in 1950; and that – to use the words of
Stephen Jay Gould – he was only a 'punctuated balance' amongst others.
(e) We shall not forget simply epistemological reasons. Indeed, what Homo calls
his ideas, his concepts and his axioms chiefly depend on the cortical areas of his brain, characterised by
their speed and determination. Hence, nothing is easier to do than speculate
and build abstract systems. At the opposite, objects and technical processes
largely depend from the deep brain, for instance the basic glands and the
cerebral trunk, which have extremely performing autonomous memory as they allow
a hairdresser or an airline pilot to remember the thousands of nuances in the
handling of a pair of scissors or a joystick. Yet, these solid teachings are
very slow to acquire and modify. Hence, abstract ideas are passed down from the
master to his disciple, sometimes in a mere moment, where many years are
necessary for a technical aptitude to be passed down from a master to his
apprentice.
(f) Still epistemologically, the order of exhibition and the
order of invention are not the same in technique and philosophy. Descartes is
so convinced of playing with 'clear and distinct' ideas and Spinoza with
'adequate ideas', that they both believe they can describe an order of
exhibition equivalent to their order of invention. And they write 'discourses
on the method', 'rules for the direction of the mind', the 'ethic demonstrated
in a geometric manner'. Their rational pretension can be found in some English
empiricism. Yet, such an illusion is not possible for a technician. Simondon
insists that, in Watt's invention of the steam machine, the crossroads between
theory and empery are so numerous, so inextricable, particularly between
preliminary analogical invention and posterior digital rectification, that a
discourse of the technical method is not probable. The Eiffel Tower is a
popular example of the part played by day-to-day working operations in the
construction-invention of technical objects.
(g) Finally, Homo's trust and defiance
towards the Technique has an ontological source. We must recall that the primordial
articulation in the Universe is the distinction: functioning / presence (s).
(Anth. Gén. Chapter
8), and that everywhere we find in Homo his favour for experiments of presence
that put the functioning in between parenthesis: music, spatial arts, religious
rites, orgasm, all the banal forms of daily drunkenness, nirvana, dikr, voodoo…
(Maslow noted all these peak experiences among students from one same University that
had all been deemed 'normal' by their peers). They are all different forms of
functioning being put in between parenthesis, sometimes by neutralizing, other
times by boosting their perceptive-motor and logico-semiotic field effects in
the comptabilisation of uncoordinables that is rhythm with its eight resources (ibidem).
However, technique stands on the side of functioning, and
the word 'rhythm' only designates the regularity of cadences. Hence, Homo
admires technique, he develops it, and in turn, each morning it gives him his
immediate goals. But it is always a bit as though it was a preliminary or a
fundament in view of something else that would solely be truly essential, the
'final cause', when for example working for
leisure. Buddha leaves the 'technical' management of a kingdom to seek the
silence of the without breadth (nir-vana) where functioning are abolished. A
Japanese general director suddenly leaves the huge factory that he has spent
his entire life building to go and watch cherry trees in blossom. It is as
though technique, as respectable as it may be, was never the last word, but
always ended up as a means, a game of ends and means. This happens even when it questions the infinite spaces around the
big bang to attempt touching, sensing the Last Word, the Ultimate Question,
which are supposed to be of another nature.
Thereby philosophers
– who are convinced in advance that technique is not final – would
have ended up forgetting just how foremost it is, how constantly primary. The
Anthropogénie is not a philosophy. It deals with origins, genesis, 'genius',
and takes into consideration the ultimate goals, but starting with their
preliminaries. Especially when these preliminaries, such as Technique, can be
more or less neutralized, boosted by 'presentive' behaviours favouring pure
presence, but that are never outdated or forgotten.
(h) We still need to specify that the
Technique has not always had the same importance in Homo's phylogenesis. Despite its powerful ascent from the
Palaeolithic to the Neolithic, the primary empires, and the Greek and Roman
rational crafts, it did not shake up Nature much; and this, since the day circa
1000, when Western Homo did not see Christ return and decided not only to obey
Nature, but also to exploit it by becoming an engineer, a co-creator alongside
the Creator Engineer. Energy machines created local perturbations while the
incommensurably more powerful forces of nature soon re-established the
compromised ecological balance. Economic and political systems held on to the
illusion that they governed the world. In 1948 still, in the Human Rights
Declaration, States proclaimed that they were 'sovereign'.
This changed with the reign
of information machines that begun soon after the Second World War. The expertise of energy
machines was slow to pass down, but the know-how of information machines is
rapidly decipherable and understandable. In the same time, it is globally
transmitted through the development of the communications it generates. In
fifty years, the couple energy-information modified the ecological balance of the
entire Planet, meaning its climates and living species. Today, technician Homo
has many of the properties of the omnipresent Engineer that he used to think as
being the Demiurge of his Universe. In 2007, he hopes that, in 2008, he will be
able to recreate several conditions of the big bang at the CERN. These
urgencies further take him away from any philosophy of the Technique, or the
opportunity to daydream in increasingly rarer moments of pure respite.
Chapter 1 - THE THREE FACES OF THE MACHINE
By approaching the history
of the technique, the sociologist has the satisfaction of finding the same
steps, whatever the envisaged viewpoint may be. Whether he is interested in the
machine for its great types of functioning, its political or artistic
incidence, or for the optimism or pessimism it triggered, the sociologist must
always consider these three eras: what comes before the industrial revolution,
the industrial revolution itself, and finally, our era. We will obviously
discuss precise dates and we will ask what facts rather than others decided of
the beginning and of the scope of the great eras. However, the global
articulations remain. Mumford gave us a classic expression by making the
distinction between an ecotechnical era right until the mid 18th century,
a paleotechnical
era covering the 19th and early 20th centuries, and a neotechnical era, which we inaugurate. [1].
We shall not escape a similar division. Perhaps the most
substantial progress of this reflection is to stop talking of the machine in general and to distinguish three stages, three violently
contrasted faces, which triggered very different cultural reactions. We cannot
go straight to the last, ours, because its predecessors still inspire our
optimist or pessimistic philosophies as they do our daily options, which may be
irritated or fascinated by it. Furthermore, the most advanced stages of a
technique still include the first as elements: the rooftop is still held in
place by the floors.
Hence, we must turn to the past in the aim of genetically
grasping the articulations, the stratifications of today's machines, and our
emotional reactions to them. In pretentious terms, our research aims to be not
historical but phenomenological and structural, as befits a coming of a
reflected culture.
1A. THE STATIC MACHINE
Paleontology dates the arrival of man and his tools. Needles
and combs made from bones, hatchets and arrows made of flint prove more, in
man's eyes, than the shape and volume of a skull. Indeed, the means of
transformation – whose internal and external relations show very well
that their functions were grasped as such, as a 'secondary' universe; the
technique – is capable in turn of being transformed and developed.
Koehler's monkey, when deciding to grasp a stick to reach a banana, invents a
transitory tool, which in this case is not one. The true tool stabilizes
itself, detaches itself, and refers to other complementary artifices and to its
own development. It supposes a power of symbolization, of objectivation, of
distance that is typical to man. The way in which its idea implies the notion
of system invites to put its development in relation with that of the system
per se: language [2].
What were the first
machine-related principles put to use? From the Palaeolithic, rupestre
representations of traps demonstrate how the animal, when touching the bottom,
would cause the fall of bevelled tree trunks. The principle of the lever was
working. Yet, the true beginning of the machine starts with the wheel during
the Neolithic era. In the interlocking of the disk and the axis, the wheel
brought a richer application of the conjugated functions and supplied the first
Antiquity for its peak. Lever and wheel, with their derivatives, the pulley,
the hoist, the gear and the turning machine, – all engines for the
reduction of forces – would suffice to carry, in war time and in peace,
the agrarian cultivations of the Nile, the Euphrates, the Ganges and the Yellow
River.
The
classic Antiquity and the first middle Ages did not require much more. For
social and religious reasons [3], the Ancients were not so much
engineers as they were astronomers and physicists, and the mechanical poverty
of their hourglasses and their clepsydras contrasts with the mathematical refinement
of their sundials. Even their vocabulary is disappointing: the Greek Mèchanè and Latin Machina refer to the aspect of cleverness,
surprise, and abrupt efficiency of the engines rather than to their mechanical
characteristics of independence and automacity [4]. If Ctesibius invents a force pump
and if Hero of Alexandria uses the pressure of heated air and water, it is
essentially to combine automatons for playful or cultural means. There is only
one area where antique technicians considered their talent with some
seriousness: war machinery and in particular torsion catapults where they
transformed the teachings of Philo of Byzantium, of Vitruvius and of Hero of
Alexandria into empiric recipes. For the rest, the Romans used Archimedes'
bucket drains for the evacuation of water in their mines. They developed the
norias and, on the eve of Christianity, watermills. Yet, these remarkable
inventions do not bring about the technical revolution that they could have.
Even in the area of architecture where they had the merit of perfecting the
grouting process, we see that the citizens of the empire continue using the
costly solution of inclined plane aqueducts, whereas in Pergamon, the
principles of communicating vessels were in place as soon as the second century
of our era. It is true that technical knowledge is not solely cumulative; it
supposes a mind that decides to exploit it or to let it go to waste. Schuhl
speaks of the 'premecanician mentality', or the 'antimecanician mentality' of
the Antiquity [5].
Around the fatidic year
1000, Western civilisation will deeply change this attitude. If, until then,
the technique aimed at ends without much considering the means, it is because
it had its slaves, a weak motor force that was expensive to feed, albeit
mobile. The fall of the Empire and the progressive reflection on the
implications of Christianity will soon put an end to this resource. Henceforth,
the first aim of the technique will be – even before the pursuit of the
result – to lighten the burden of man and the effect was that it greatly
favoured the results and the West then launches into a prodigious research and
exploitation of exterior forces. The strength of the animal in the hardware and
the harness; physical forces in the endless development of hydraulic wheels,
the windmills of Islam, the sails of ships. The forces of regulation in the
fixed steer and the pedal loom, chemical forces in gunpowder and particularly
in the distillation of sulphuric and nitric acids, the aggregates of metalwork,
all this leading to the use of light, iodine supports: colourless glass, the
milieu of chemical reactions, and paper, soon conjoined to mobile characters
and the printers' press [6].
Yet, these conquests, which
take place between the 10th and the 13th centuries,
almost fade before another contemporary conquest [7], the mechanical clock. The event is
one of history's most considerable, where Spengler sees the symbol of a new
culture, as the regular chiming and the hand on the dial demonstrate an
obsession for the exact and efficient length that was unknown to the Chinese,
the Indians and the Greek and that penetrates all our creations. Munford dates
the 'geotechnical' era from this invention and underlines the fact that the
clock, engendered by the monasteries' need for regularity, were about to
provide the western man with this abstract, rigid framework that was independent
from the seasons and that would lead him to conceive the past as such (let us
recall the historical resurrections of the Renaissance, Classicism and
Romanticism), to place himself rigorously into space (let us look at the
compass, the sailing compass, cartography, territorial explorations) and to be
interested in pure greatnesses and powers (the elements of capitalism), and
finally, to engender these concentrates of precision, regularity,
synchronisation, and acceleration: our machines.
From a machine-related
viewpoint, escapement is not a simple progress, but it is a mutation. Nothing
in the triggering of the bow or the catapult or in the rhythmic swaying of the noria
can forecast the idea of this oscillation, which alternatively holds and frees
the movement [8] . Henceforth, the new mechanic mind is born. From now on, it will be
possible to envisage the indefinite repetition of an identical action using a
winding system. It will be possible to combine a succession of different
actions in advance: in its germ, the clock contains not only the perpetual
Strasbourg calendar, but all the automatons that will characterise the Swiss
clock making of the 17th and 18th centuries. And if all
this gratuitous virtuosity was looked down upon, let us recall that the
process, in the form of the jumper, feeds Pascal's arithmetic machine and that
the cam, which belongs to the same mind, is at the source of all our modelling
engines.
Such was in substance the
technique from its origins to the 1750's. Indeed, the great scientific
discoveries of the Renaissance and the Baroque only produced some industrial
applications much later. We can see its culmination in 18th century
navigation. Seeing the position of their colonies, the Portuguese and the
Spanish would sail along the coasts to reach the latitude of the targeted
country, and would then follow the parallel calculated by the angular height of
the Polar star using a process that was already known by the Greek. Because of their rivalry, and because
their colonies were in high latitudes where the parallel makes a noticeable
detour, the French and the English launched into a severe competition to
achieve a navigation in straight line that demanded the delicate calculation of
longitudes. They needed either chronometers or optical instruments whose
refinement used turning and dividing machines, the ancestors of every tooling.
Armed with these precious clocking precisions, redoubtable artillery and
prodigious sailing force, a vessel of the admiralty of Louis XVI summarises the
ancient technique [9].
Had the machine remained at
that mechanical stage where it only transmitted movements either directly or
indirectly [10], it would not have caused a problem, and we do not see how the
philosophers of the time would have felt it to be much of a concern. They had
only conceived it as it was, as every other tool or utensil, an artificial
object that was by essence the opposite of living or mineral beings, an object
that had a somewhat particular causality, one that Aristotle called
instrumental. They did not give it much consideration, as they did not much
consider anything that was related to practical realisation or manual work,
which were not worth a free man. It was nothing for them to be concerned with [11]What was a pulley, a hoist, a catapult, a ram, or even a clock or a pump, if
not the prolonged gesture of a limb similar to our limbs, similar to an arm
that coils, empties, balances, turns, to the hand that buckles, grasps, lets go
in rhythm? And it is indeed the image of the accrued body that is most often
alleged by theoreticians. In fact, the almost exclusively used material was
wood. It is the most docile and the closest material to the human body (whilst
steel with the violence of the miner and the blacksmith) [12] was still the
exception. As for the windmills and sailing boats, if they did anything else
than prolong a gesture, they also captured the most familiar elements very
visibly. Orators, poets, decorators and liturgists had there, during thousands
of years, an endless arsenal of images that were reassuring and understood by
all. The natural character is so particular to these forms of energy that it
explains both its quality and its flaw: a very high turnover contrasting with
the wastefulness of steam engines and the irregularities linked to the whims of
the seasons.
The teaching mode
reinforced cosmic sympathy: the latter, which was intuitive, consisted in the
acquisition of dexterity. Things were supposed to conceal mysterious powers
that the artisan would free in an intimate contact that resembled a taming. The
modeller tested the clay with the palm of his hand and the peasant knew the
earth and the rain in a touch that spread to his entire body.
The interposition of the
tool and the machine did not change much. These instruments of contacts
participated to the proximity of the worker's gesture. Hence the initiatory
character of the teaching both with the primitives and in our corporations,
which conclude the testimony of the ancient machine by binding man to society
and nature. Dexterity supposed the direct and daily commerce of the master,
from whom the 'mastery' was passed down in a kind of filiation. Similar work
relations engendered generally stable and warm social structures despite
inequalities. We only note one revolution since the Antiquity, which was quite
content to submit to the order of the world until the Renaissance, impatient to
exploit it. For Francis Bacon, the technique was 'mankind added to nature', and
does not include the merest idea of violence, at the opposite of Descartes'
perception. In their opinion, we act upon it – more in desire than in
actions – by acting like it, according to a formula used by Marsile Ficin.
This image will seem
idyllic for the end of that period. New industries – mining, glass, and
printing – owe much to capitalism, which was quick to subtract them from
the social rules of the corporation. On the other hand, it is in musketry that
appeared, for the very first time, the advantages of mass production that
engendered collusion between technique and militarism that meant that
campaigning armies and an industry ready for wartime became the ideal of many
technicians. Finally, the beneficial growth of the demand depended of (through
the bourgeois luxury) the great courtesans [13]. Yet, these doubtful alliances
concern more the atmosphere favourable to the eotechnical object than itself
and do not compromise the reassuring picture that we have painted. Capitalism,
militarism and luxury of the court all introduced flaw while they maintained a
considerable cultural meaning, as the urbanistic realisations of the 17th
century testify.
When the great
encyclopaedia is published around 1700, it is both the conclusion and the
apotheosis of this era [14].
We shall not waste a minute in saying that it already
announced – in more than one aspect – the new age. It inaugurated
the scientific comprehension of the machine by enlightening the laws of
mechanic set up by Galilee, Descartes, Leibniz, Newton, and therefore went
beyond the fortuitous and non-communicable skills of earlier technicians. But
it is one of these exceptional moments when humanity slides from one phase to
another by conjugating benefits and by neutralising the drawbacks one by one.
The machine is scientific. Yet, it remains intuitive. It does not abolish
dexterity. Rather, it explains it and makes it transparent, joining body and
reason. This wonderful, precarious balance culminates in the fifteen volumes of
plates that all speak to the mind, the eye, and to the gesture while conjoining
the virtues of the number, which will be the world to come – unbeknownst
to Da Vinci – with the simultaneous grasping of the outlook that Da Vinci
– the perfect Renascent – had exhaled as the supreme fruition. All
this remains at the level of man, right to the appearance: the machine looks
like a piece of furniture in the house, unless that, windmill for the miller,
it is the house itself… Furthermore, in its illustrative aspect, what is the
Encyclopaedia if not the ideal workshop where all the machines would have
gathered in a closed order, at hand's reach, in the semi-mental form of
printing?
However, we must repeat
that it is a transition. By penetrating the science machine, it exposed it to
become the instrument of an abstract production that would escape man's
measure. Simultaneously, it took away the initiatory character from the
teaching and put it at the reach of anyone capable of providing an effort. It
shook up every corporative privilege and the entire ancient regime. Therefore,
the Encyclopaedia is a direct prelude to the Industrial Revolution and to the
French Revolution. It concludes the first age of the machine as it opens the
second.
1B. THE DYNAMIC MACHINE
No one agrees as to the
beginnings of the Industrial Revolution. At one time, it was fashionable to see
it as one of the consequences of the Napoleonic wars that stimulated discovery
and – through the national armies and their complex logics – placed
Western Europe in a state of industrialisation. Uneasy with this unflattering
thesis for humanity, pacifist historians such as John U. Nef underlined to the
contrary that the dices had been thrown as soon as 1785 and that it was more
appropriate to invoke the exceptional era of peace of the 18th
century, first attempt of a united Europe [15].
Indeed, the Industrial Revolution has distant ancestors in both war and
peace. Its most characteristic engines – the steam machine, the coal high
furnace, the automatic loom – are the result of hundreds of individual
inventions whose path can be traced back to the 17th century, the
Renaissance, and even before. And we know that capitalism –the luxuries
of the court and the militarist regime –, which would favour the
industrial mentality, had former credentials. For we must understand that this
Revolution was as much a general climate as a machine-related effervescence. If
the need for a good turnover steam machine is increasingly pressing in 18th
century England, it is because important commercial problems increasingly faced
the spinners who were overwhelmed by the demand of the weavers, or affected the
weavers that could not follow the orders of the spinners. This alternative was
exasperated by a strange law that suppressed – for some time – all
the taxes on Indian cottons and silks in an aim to deliberately whip up English
textile. Therefore, the Industrial Revolution appears like a confluent where
the technique (steel puddling in 1783), the economy (suppression of the last
privileges of the corporations and extension of the markets under the influence
of Smith's liberalism), external (the Indian colonies) and internal policies
(exodus of English peasants towards the cities under the pressure of
gentlemen-farmers), all of which were animated by what we really ought to call
the new mentality [16],
où and in which Calvinist fervour played a great part [17].
Regardless of its era and
causes, the machine shows a new face circa 1800. It ceases to be an innocent
means to somewhat lighten human tasks and ensure – against all odds
– a day-to-day subsistence, and it starts appearing like an indefinite
power instrument aimed at satisfying equally indefinite needs. We can pinpoint
this mutation with the passage from the Newcomen machine to Watt's machine.
With the Newcomen, the effect of steam was to push back the piston, then pushed
by the atmospheric pressure. The work depended of a – naturally limited –
natural force, the weight of air. We were still in the world of wind and water
mills. Watt turns the problem around. Henceforth, the steam will push, assuming
engine time, and, as its power can indefinitely be increased, it is also
indefinitely multipliable [18].
Consequently, the commands are passed from nature to man. Energetism
– which will soon be developed by thermodynamic and electro dynamism
– is born. It will find a powerful ally in an old principle that takes a
new departure at its contact: organisation. And the machine that – since
its origins – had not alerted men of culture, started to inspire a moral,
almost a religion: the religion of efficiency, quality, result, and progress,
through the brutal force of the steam machine, and through the organised force
of the loom or the telephone. Having conjugated these two grandeurs, the
railway became the masterpiece of the era.
There were the optimists who
promised a universal statute to steam, and soon to electricity and petrol. Marx
could well see that these new engines alienated the proletariat, that they
favoured the 'degrading division of work'. However, in his eyes, it was a
transitory inconvenient that was essentially linked to the power of capitalism.
To see better days, it would be enough to knock capitalism over and to give the
worker possession of his work tools. Someone like Berthelot was more confident
still when he considered that the new instruments applicable to the chemical
synthesis that he promoted would not only fill the material needs of the human
being but would inevitably engender (through overabundance) a political regime
that would ensure happiness and virtue. He was constructing the economy of a
revolution where Marx saw a stepping-stone that was everywhere necessary.
Yet, the vast majority of
men of culture were sombre as they felt that the disadvantages of what they
were beginning to call the modern world were tied to its very being. There was
the long complaint of the poets, from Vigny to Rilke, going through the furore
of Nietzsche. Flaubert attempted to grasp the century and proved that it was
possible to raise to the style the ancient Carthage or Alexandria, or even the
more traditional province of Madame Bovary, but not what there was – both
in intuitions and things – that was purely 19th century.
Indeed, the failure of the Education Sentimentale preludes that of naturalism.
Painters, who were more radical, decided to silence a world that they did not
understand; the workshops of the Renaissance stepped in Dürer's paintings, and
the windmills of the 17th century in Rembrandt's. The locomotive,
despite Turner's first enthusiasm, only became pictorial through the fog of
impressionism [19].
However, architects and engineers had great confidence in steel and
concrete, although they usually used them to simply render characterless and
ancient architecture bigger. This general state of helplessness is well
expressed in the contradictions of the aestheticians of the era who float
between the bare truth of true functionalism, indigent seeing the elementarily
of the machine of the era, and the untruth of the ornament that will result in
the Modern Style.
Yokes are supported by Corinthian columns or hidden behind tapestries [20].
Ruskin is probably logical when he preaches the fleeing of a world he
sees as degraded and a return to nature, the source of life. His opinion is
shared by less aesthetic moralists. In the myth of Erewhon, in 1872, Butler, who supposes that
the machines obey to Darwin's natural selection and that they have arrived to
hound man, offers the lone salvaging measure: their destruction.
Assuredly, we find many
prejudices and ignorance in these viewpoints. But then again, a condemnation
that is so unanimous and that persists for such a long time undoubtedly aims
further than the political flaws denounced by Marx. It had to be linked to the
deep character of these new objects. To express the uneasiness, was it enough
to say that Pittsburgh's environment of smoke, dust and sludge would place the
rich boss in a situation that was almost as gloomy as his starved workers?
That, for the very first time in history, an entire civilisation rested on the
mine, the most inhumane and backward of industries. That the cult of production
demanded that everyone show a contention that would engender the down to earth
small mindedness of Victorian morals and a barbarian conception of school,
ensuring training but also the depersonalising discipline required by the new
jobs [21] ?
The explanation is all too
simple. In this regard, countries are very different, and Germany never knew
the monstrous excesses of England [22]. Furthermore, hideousness characterises the dynamic machine in the
couple coal-steel of its beginnings, but fades away in the couple electricity-aluminium
in 1850 and in the couple petrol-special metals from 1880. Electrical apparel
invites cleanliness, finesse, and geometry. Electricity, which is easily
transportable in every corner of the workshop or the region, suggests
industrial decentralisation by freeing the machines from the propeller shaft of
the steam machine [23]. Petrol has the same effect and, as
it allows the automobile, it frees the town centres, saturated by the fatal
convergence of railway lines. Does all this not plead in favour of a frank,
clean life? Munford was so convinced of this that, after Lenin, he saw the
possibility of a new era in electrification, petrol and the telephone, a
'neotechnical era' that would relay the 'paleotechnical' era of coal and steel
under the condition that men should draw the economic and political
consequences of these new powers. Under the angle of ugliness, dirt and
fatigue, the flaws of the dynamic machine would seem to be correctible and not
linked to its very being. However, the critics were not satisfied with so
little. They did not lean their essential argumentation on the ugliness and
brutalities or the social injustices. Contrary to the opinion of Munford, they
deemed that a complete passage to electricity – if it were at all
possible – would not solve the problem. What is the problem, if we try to
go back to before these clumsy, passionate formulations?
1B1. The dynamic energy machine
The 19th century
energetic machine is in complete break with man and nature. The mechanical
machine that preceded it prolonged the human body and natural forces: mills,
sailing boats, and even pumps and presses captured wind and water according to
their own output, putting them to work without disguise, using them on site [24]. At the opposite, the locomotive,
the high furnace, the electrical turbine and the internal combustion engine not
only isolate the worker but also, instead of blending in with natural forces,
stir them in every possible way. They transmute them from a form into another,
whether it is mechanical, thermal, electrical, or chemical. In this context,
the concept of energy and the principle of its consecration will be discovered,
transporting them everywhere without any reminder of their origin. Hence the
feeling – that some witnesses expressed – of finding oneself before
a new being that, even when it was not as frightening as the first high
furnaces or guilty of rape as the factory and the railway that violated the
landscape, remained inassimilable through the culture and value systems,
because we only knew of man, of nature and of the few objects binding the two.
After the semi-artificial engines of the past, the energetic machine is a
consumed artifice that forms a strange reign, away from everything.
Furthermore, a means only
seems natural to us when it is visibly linked to a concrete end: grinding
wheat, lifting a stone at the top of a wall, or dyeing a garment. This was the
case of the mechanical machine whose energy was polyvalent by right (it could
be used for a thousand things) but was in fact limited to a task to which it
was no longer 'dedicated'. The energetic machine severs this link. Its end is
no longer the accomplishment of a concrete action but to produce energy in
general. It is a means to a means. It inaugurates the reign of the pure means,
which is as distant from man as it is from nature, as strange – some will
say monstrous – as the reign of the pure artifice.
On top of its strangeness,
it also has something that is aggressive for the living. Whilst it changes its
mind, adapts ever-renewed operations and works through synthesis and
continuity, it goes straight ahead, endlessly repeating the same action,
analysing its processes thoroughly. This was tolerated in the slow ticking of
the clock and the mill, reminiscent of vital rhythms, but in the hundredfold
speed of concentrations of energy, it shows a scary face, the face of raw
matter. The linear thrust, the numeric multiplication, the analytical
fragmentation are the very characters of materiality. Under the effect of
acceleration, they take a relief, a purity that comes from the to-and-fro of
the piston, of the rod and the wheel, the vertiginous antipode of life. The
deep shame is that such blindness is often more efficient than its flexibility.
The living felt dispossessed.
The only thing the living
could do was to force himself to adopt the invader's way of being. We shall not
dwell on chain work that gives the gesture a stereospecificity where man models
himself on the machine, where man 'serves' the machine in countdown
instrumentation. It is a consequence that is inscribed in the logic of the
energy but it is one that perhaps does not belong to its essence. By right, it
also tends to reduce the tasks of the labourer. The influence on the
intelligence of the user, the worker, and even the inventor was much more
fundamental. Indeed, the energy machine does not belong to the lived experience
of the ancient dexterity, nor does it belong to a true scientific knowledge.
There is nothing scandalous there, we shall say, because, between the non
criticised function
of empiric and the critical fact of science, there is room for a third order:
that of the criticised function, which belongs to modern technique [25]. But precisely, in the dynamist world, the function reduced to itself
(the means of a means) is so poor, so material, that it was never able to
define its own territory in the kingdom of knowledge. We observe that most of
the technicians of the era hesitated between the status of empirical finders,
and that – less glorious – of the simple appliers of scholarly
theories. To this, we must attribute (more than to a pretend modesty or
incapability of expression) that 19th century technicians found
themselves in trade-related problems and hated going into any general idea of
the technique, except to affirm a thoughtless faith in quantitative progress
or, more often, to situate themselves outside of culture, (in their eyes) the
territory of the philosopher, the literary, the artist, and recently, the man
of science [26].
In turn, this state of
things affected social relations. Assuredly, it is difficult to set apart the
abuse of capitalism as criticised by Marx and the crimes of the energy machine.
Yet, the classes engendered by economic structures were soon joined by three
other classes, which were equally 'alienating'. The businessman uses it to economic
or political ends, in a manner that is particularly arbitrary that it does not
have any intrinsic finality. It is therefore questioned by this arbitrary
itself and by his ignorance towards the instruments on which he leans and that
he must content with exploiting. The technician, engineer or foreman
understands his instruments – although he feels that he is a scholarly
bastard – but in return he is excluded from the decision of the ends,
extrinsic to the machine and under the responsibility of the businessman or the
politician. Finally, the worker, simple working livestock, is excluded from the
true comprehension of the machine apart from that of the pursued objective. The
proof that these characters are linked to the energetic mechanic statute is that
we find them in Stalinian Russia, where the arbitrary of the businessman
– the planner – is illustrated by what the Russian critics have
since baptized 'economic subjectivism', the uneasiness of the technician
through the drama of the intelligentsia, the functioning livestock of the work
camps [27]. The social disarray is best found
in the era's architectural dispersion. Apart from a few policing-inspired urban
attempts like Haussmann's in Paris, never has the space of the house, the city,
or the road been more incoherent than in the 19th century.
Finally, the adversaries of
the dynamist machine deemed it harmful right down to its cultural advantages.
One by one, they rejected the three arguments brought forth by its rare
defenders, in particularly American technocrats of the 1920's [28].
You say that the machine increases leisure? But speaking of the sort
means accepting a dichotomy where true life is nowhere, not in the work, not
preparatory to leisure, nor in the leisure, which, deprived of articulations
around work, empties of substance. It frees work from sordid constraints and,
with the developments of electricity and special metals, goes as far as to
dress it with an aesthetic order and functionality. To humanize a work, it is
not enough to lighten it, but it must be made significant. Yet, the aesthetic
of the styling,
if reduced to the finish of the matter, to the round of the form and to a
certain reminiscence of living being as invoked by Mumford, does not promise
anything more than a vain rest for the eyes. There is little to expect from the
functionality if the function of the means-to-means is devoid of spiritual
content. The energy machine comprises the suppression of rarity [29] hence privileges and social classes. To
the contrary, we have just seen that it implicates a new division in classes
– the class of the businessman, the technician, and the executer –
that is even more alienating than its predecessor. Whichever way we look at it,
we are at the wheel…
1B2. The dynamic order machine
The technical world does
not only have energy machines. It needs machine that produce forms,
arrangements that are more spatial than in modelling machines [30],
that are more temporal in the information machines. The 19th
century was wealthy in both genres. It perfected the loom, mechanised printing,
the sower and the reaper. It was revolutionary by creating the telegraph, the
telephone, the cinema, and the radio.
Still, in its information
machines, the technical world only saw a new means to activate its modelling
machines from a distance. In these machines, it only saw an indirect way to
favour his production of energy even more. It did not perceive the technical
originality of information, which is that it can speculate over time and manage
actions in return. It did not grasp the originality of order as a universal,
physical and technical principle that is distinct from energy. In every way, it remains energetic. It
is hardly surprising that here too it was open to reproaches. In its technical
use of machines of order, we find everywhere the acceleration of linear
movements that are recurrent, analytic, the means-of-means, the dependency of
man to his tool.
Yet, what can be said of
the manner in which the late 19th century and the early 20th
century used the press, the phonograph, the cinema, the radio – and very
soon, television – to multiply directly cultural realities, the text, the
voice, the music, and the gesture? Was it not bringing to the life of the mind
– apart from a democratic broadcast – the intense and varied
exchanges that sociologists have always considered as its main engine? Even
here the critics did not give in. Culture is an artifice, they say. Its end is
to put us in contact with the real. Yet, the proliferating information screens
both mind and things, and in this sense, it is passive. Not that it would provoke
somnolence, but the activity that it triggers mainly targets the substitutes of
reality, images, sounds, words, and phantasms that all too soon become ghosts [31].
Let us not prejudge anything.
Perhaps that one day soon we will have to admit that, transported in another
context, broadcasting takes on an unexpected character of truth. But then, it
will no longer be simply quantitative multiplications.
In fact, the common trait
of dynamic engines – whether of order or of energy – was clearly
expressed by the Bergsonian philosophy that concludes the period: they are
abstract [32].
The metamorphosed energy is an abstraction; it is torn away from its
natural milieu and has become means-of-means. It is an abstraction that the
repetition and the stereotyped succession made purely numerical through the
effect of acceleration. Training, which is neither truly intuitive nor truly
scientific, in the same way as the attached economic-social and urban
relationships, is an abstraction. Information, which turns on itself, screening
the world instead of revealing it, is an abstraction. Bergson does not
explicitly draft the theory of the dynamic machines, but we can sense that
these machines shape his environment when he opposes quantity to quality, the
'all done' to the 'doing', determinism to freedom, inert time to lived length.
If he wants to reign, man needs these servants that will reduce him to slavery [33],
Hence, it is essential that he should
promote and control them, seeking in their gathering a 'supplement of soul'.
These analysis and those of
the innumerable pessimistic essayists that follow [34],
are still very much alive because
the dynamic machine – like the static machine before – is a
constant of the technician world, and its ideal of purely quantitative
efficiency will exert its fascination over some minds for a very long time
still. Bergson's sole mistake (and particularly his successors') is that he
extended his criticism of one state of the machine to the machine in general.
Not only did he and his followers lose sight that it could be subject to a
metamorphosis, but they also forgot that it had known, in its origins, a much
less redoubtable status. Yet, how could they think about that as they were
submerged under new machines?
If we are more careful and
if we look more closely, we shall see that, before the Industrial Revolution,
technical objects had a very different status. We will understand that we must
distinguish these two ages because we are inaugurating a third age, one that
directly controls our future.
1C. THE DIALECTIC MACHINE
We are witnessing what is
commonly accepted as a second Industrial Revolution. Yet, we still need to
determine what it lies in. We are generally content with stressing that nuclear
forces have given our energy machines a prodigious leap and that our
information machines have gone from the still elementary stage of the telephone
to that of calculators and cybernetic engines. And we can effortlessly
demonstrate a huge increase of both power and precision: support before the oil
and coal layers ran out (something that haunted the consciousness of the 19th
century), mobility allowing for the improvement of deserted regions and
decentralisation of the others [35]; perfection of the settings that increase the qualities of
the finish and the proportion that Mumford saw in electrical apparels. But if
things were to stay still from our cultural viewpoint, would we be much better
off? In such a perspective, technique remains accountable for every accusation
of anti-humanism accumulated against the dynamic machine, which remains suspect
even in its advantages.
Thankfully,
it is the place for a deeper mutation. Gilbert Simondon remarked that every
technical object is engaged in a concretisation process, meaning that in the
start, it is articulated in isolated functions and organs that are analytically
distinct and that it tends to conjoin them, establishing concomitances,
interrelations, and synergies between them [36]. But then, it is plausible that some objects present such a
rate of abstraction that they appear and are known as abstract despite their
concreteness whilst others present such a rate of concreteness that they appear
and are said to be concrete in spite of their abstraction. We should like to
characterise the present machine-related change using a similar mutation of
rates. Whilst the 19th century machine (which was still analytical,
linear and juxtaposed) seemed globally abstract and deserved every reproach
that have since stuck to abstraction, our machine, in an ever-increasing number
of cases, discovers enough synergies for concreteness to move to the forefront,
taking with it a deep change of its cultural sense. We even feel that with this
new face, it explains – or in any event reinforces – most of the
essential characters of the contemporary world; that it suggests a value system
susceptible of promoting a new humanism.
Hence defined, dating the
second Industrial Revolution is no easier task than defining a date for the
first. An energetic scheme as concrete as the Diesel goes back to 1893-97; a
concrete cybernetic scheme like feedback also begins with Watt in the 18th
century. However, let us not forget that far from the first trace of a
technical discovery is its cultural glow. It has to become a daily object.
Using other words, it must be industrialised. It is increasingly important that
is should no longer offer a simple fact but a principle with its own
fecundities. Therefore, as soon as 1780, Watt equipped his steam engine with a
ball-type governor. When the machine turned without gripping, the balls were
lifted by the centrifuge force and acted on a lever that would partly interrupt
the entry of steam. Assuredly, such a device offers an example of retroactive
action where an effect (the movement of the piston) acts on its cause (the
entry of steam) to regulate it. There we have the feedback that we are so proud
of! But it is completely different to invent a device enforcing a principle
than laying down the principle itself. So Watt does not invent the feedback, he
invents a mechanism that includes a feedback. We shall have to wait until 1868
for Maxwell to analyse this rigorously. Then, we will have to wait many more
years before physiologists clearly recognise a structure of our nervous
assembling. Then, we wait for some more until finally, with our contemporary
cyberneticists, the feedback takes on the dignity of a universal scheme of
functioning. Still, before truly being part of humanism, the man of culture
must see the invention, and he will transform it into common categories. We can
see that the road is long. It is even longer when some steps are skipped. Diesel,
when he creates the spark-ignition engine, immediately made a reasoned
invention by taking away its principle [37]. Some rare humanists have now understood that it concerns
them.
When we consider these
precisions, we can affirm that the concrete thought was rearing its head in the
early 20th century when the First World War triggered a gigantic
comeback of the most dynamist mentality. This comeback proved to be destructive
during the conflict and constructive after it, and incurred the sad
consequences that we know in the great crisis of 1930, which demonstrated the
impasses of pure dynamism and would have perhaps been enough to promote the synergic
preoccupations that were put aside, as we see in the American technocracy. In
any event, the latter were brought to the front of the scene by a new worldwide
conflict with its brutal clearings and need for instantaneous riposte demanding
the dazzling progress of the radar, anti-air cannons, and operational research.
The world took a new face that it held onto during peacetime. In short, the
concrete mentality definitely joins the definition of cybernetic with the team
of Norbert Wiener in 1948 [38],
for information
machines, and in the aforementioned thoughts of Simondon in 1958 for energy
machines.
1C1. The dialectic energy machine
The concreteness or
synergies of our engines are applicable to them all and demonstrate their
unity. However, since some are more obvious in energy machines and others in
information machines, we shall classify them between these two types for an
easier comprehension.
1C1a. Synergy of functions
The body of an airplane
must respond to at least three requirements: it must be rigid, offer a decent
surface of sustentation, and break the air effortlessly. The early apparels
dating back to the early 20th century had a carcass conferring them
rigidity and a coating granting them the surface of sustentation. Yet, this
distinction between the coating and the carcass imposed a weight and an angular
form that were not compatible with breaking the air. In today's airplanes, the
coating is streamlined in such a way that it is self-carrying, as the pressures
that exert in one plan reel at the average curve, so much so that it can
decrease the work of the carcass, sometimes even suppress it. Simultaneously,
it improves its surface of sustentation and makes the breaking of air easier,
since self-carrying, aerodynamic forms are ideal in this regard. Hence, we are
here in the presence of three functions, once of which, the coating,
accomplishes a good part of the two others, i.e. sustentation and breaking. We
should even note that, by accomplishing them almost on its own – hence
largely suppressing the antagonism that systematically occurs between two
distinct organs – it perfects them. This is a case of simple versatility,
which we will call a first-degree synergy.
Yet, some are more complex.
The cylinder and the yoke of an internal combustion or combustion engine must
provide a rigid volume that resists to the internal pressures. On the other
hand, they must evacuate the heat provoked by these pressures. In the old
engines, both functions were designed separately. The thickening of the
cylinder and the yoke ensured rigidity, and a current of cold water dragging
the heat ensured the cooling. Air-cooling is synergic. Along the cylinder –
and particularly in the region of the valves – the cooling blades
intervene, ensuring the thermal dissipation. Yet, when they are properly spread
out, they also guarantee the rigidity of the volume, which used to be obtained
by the thickening of the walls. These blades also work as support ribs. In
return, their rib work allows making the wall of the cylinder thinner and also
contributes to the thermal dissipation, which is already ensured by their blade
role [39]. In the same way as with the coating of the airplane, these
blade-ribs show us a function that accomplishes another by accomplishing
itself: it is their simple versatility, or first-degree synergy. By
accomplishing this second function, they perfect the first. We then speak of
circular versatility or of second-degree synergy.
The physiology of our
machines presents the same outline as their anatomy. In last century's internal
combustion engine, the various operations are articulated in clearly distinct
places and moments. First, the fuel is blended to the combustive air in the
carburettor. Then, the hence carburetted mixture is introduced into the
combustion chamber. Then, the spark plug lights under the action of an organ
that is again distinct, the battery. Finally, the lighting of the spark plug
provokes the deflagration of the carburetted mixture that activates the piston.
In Diesel's internal combustion engine that opens the 20th century,
these moments and places conjugate. It is indeed the injection of the
combustible into the compressed air by the return of the piston that mixes it
to the air (the role of the carburettor), lights it (role of the spark plug),
and pushes back the piston (motor role of the deflagration). These are
first-degree synergies. But we could find some second-degree synergies too.
Whereas in the internal combustion engine there is a marked antagonism between
the compression and the deflagration, since the latter – under the effect
of the pressure – risks transforming itself into a detonation, in the
Diesel, since the compression is the source of the deflagration, it reduces the
antagonism between the deflagration and its effects that in turn provokes it.
Thereby, it can increase itself by increasing it.
ÉCHAPPEMENT ADMISSION
Let us note that the
progress of concreteness is not always rectilinear. In the recent Wankel
engine, some synergies of the Diesel were abandoned. We go back to the spark
plug ignition and to pre-carburation. There was still an antagonism between the
properties of piston engines and turbines. The first run economically using
petrol, and the easy transportation of the latter is well suited to the
automobile, although they experience every loss of energy inherent to the
brutal to-and-fro of the piston with its dual break. Turbines do not present
these drawbacks, but only economically run using water or steam in reduced
units, which, for the time being at least, makes them ill-suited for the
automobile. Wankel [40] imagined a
triangular rotor locked in a flattened cylinder. The three chambers created
between the rotor and the cylinder serve the first to the admission and the
initial compression of the carburetted mixture, the second for the maximal
compression and its explosion, the third to its expansion and its evacuation.
The revolution of the rotor that is provoked by the deflagration takes the
carburetted mixture, compresses it, and accelerates its exhaust after its power
stroke. Furthermore, it directly moves the axle, which is the soul of the fixed
gear on which the rotor moves. Hence, Wankel designed a configuration of the
piston that makes simultaneous and reconciles the formerly antagonistic
functions of motor compression and expansion, and conjoins them both with a
third function that used to be incompatible, the direct rotation of an axle.
The Wankel engine is a very
good demonstration that it is artificial to consider separately the anatomy and
the physiology of our engines since they are often in synergy among themselves.
The classic airplane engine propels the aircraft as it spins the propeller.
However, its body needed to conquer the air resistance in pure loss. The two
functions of propulsion (physiological) and breaking (anatomical) were
antagonist. The ramjet reconciles them: the air pressure at the entry of the
divergent ensures, by compression, the combustion of the kerosene, whose gases
lead to the propulsive effect by escaping the convergent.
It would be possible to
lengthen the list of all these examples, particularly in electrical machine
where, initially, enough precautions could not be taken to isolate the
different organs from each other for fear that their fields should perturb each
other. Rather than isolating the fields, the contemporary electrical or
electronic machine attempts to conjugate them into one unique action. Simondon
demonstrated all sorts of synergies that the passage of Crookes' tube into
Coolidge's tube proposes in the production of x-rays, or in engines of
amplification, that of Fleming's diode to Lee de Forest's triode, then to the
tetrode and the pentode [41].
For the time being, we
shall stick to a simple description, as this is not the place for underlining
the cultural scope of all of this. Yet, if we remember the great distress that
the machine caused in the dynamic era because of its opposition to life, we can
easily imagine the scope of a transformation that, by reconciling what had
previously been separated under the form of a context, gives it some
characteristics of the human being, filled with first and second degree
synergies. This kinship through the functioning goes way beyond the simple
assimilation by appearances that is 'reminiscent' of life where Mumford already
perceived a sensitive progress in 1934. Henceforth, on both sides, there is an
organic idea, a prevalence of the whole over the part where the part is no
longer simply a part but becomes an organ.
1C1b. Synergy of the machine and nature
In the same way as it
isolated its functions to realise them with more purity, the 19th
century machine worked on the exterior ambient nature: it transformed it as it
avoided a transformation in return. The ancient locomotive rushed ahead,
enduring resistance to air in pure loss, unwillingly. To propel the aircraft,
airplane propellers would determine an acceleration of the air upstream that
was wasted in turbulence.
Our fast cars improve the
use of air resistance to improve their road holding. In a recent model of
airplane, the Bréguet 941, a light coating of the synchronous propellers allow
to uniformly steer, on the wings, the debit of the air accelerated to increase
the lift. In both these cases, the first function of the machine (the
propelling) provokes a reaction of milieu that, far from being damaging or vain
as it used to be, favours another function in return (adherence or
sustentation). The positive synergy no longer plays mechanical functions
between the organs or the functions, but between the machine and its milieu.
Furthermore, we see in this
order some synergies that we could define as being negative. Thanks to its
versatility [42],
the Guimbal generator can entirely be immersed with its
turbine into the pressure pipeline of the barrage wall. Yet, if the liquid flux
accelerates, it will also accelerate the propellers of the turbine, the effect
of which is to heat up the latter, but also to increase its own turbulence,
facilitating the evacuation of heat. The stream flow is taken in a mechanism
where it is both a principle of heat and cold. It is no longer an action that
increases another in order to grow itself. The problem is less linked to the
increase than to the settings. The machine and the milieu are in circular
causality of regulation.
We are a long way away from
the dynamist rape, but are not back to the simple prolongation of natural
forces characterising the static machine. Reconciliation occurs: it is an
active reconciliation based on reciprocal causalities that gives birth to what
Simondon calls an 'associated milieu' [43].
The water around the Guimbal turbine, the air around the
fast car or between the propeller and the wing of the Bréguet 941 are not
machines; nor are they simple nature; they form a median reality with the machine. This type of
reality will only need to grow to become more spectacular – and we shall
soon see some examples – for its cultural incidence, the fading away of
the ancient, unmovable Nature, to become blatantly obvious.
1C1c. Synergy of the matter and the form
When Aristotle
distinguished a 'matter' and a 'form' in every finished being, he took his
inspiration from the technical objects lying around him. Any object or machine
from yesteryear resulted from a configuration imprinted into a material. Whether it was an
antique pulley or a 19th century steam engine, we could find
everywhere a structure and a receptacle, and between the two lay the separation
characterising abstract technique [44].
In front of our
thermometers or our germanium transistors, it has become impossible to consider
the germanium as in what the form of the instrument incarnates. It is itself what is most
original in the form through the intimacy of its electronic structure.
Similarly, the tungsten in the anticathode of a Coolidge tube is not simply placed in such a way as to allow x-rays;
its high atomic number and its high resistance to fusion constitutes the fabric
of the device and its idea. In our electronic engines, and in those that
enforce nuclear energy [45],
the 'material' and the 'formal' are conjugated and
sometimes even go as far as exchanging their roles.
Let us apply the same
observation to this other matter of a machine: the combustible. The form of
yesterday's locomotive made do with using heat, whatever its origin, according
to the exteriority of the abstraction. Hence, it burned just about anything and
only chose coal by commodity. At the opposite, our rapid engines burn their
combustible by introducing what is most particular into the most particular of
their structure. They have become most exclusive in their choice, according to
the demands of concreteness [46].
Can we say that matter and
form are in synergy in all of these examples? Assuredly, and we were perhaps
too quick in stating that they incorporated and merged. In reality, they figure
distinct poles of tension insofar as the matter ceases to be pure passivity to
take a machine-related originality in its fabric. They fecund one another: the
function of the form accomplishes itself even better that it gives the matter
an almost formal task and reciprocally; we find our second-degree positive
synergies. As these interactions – in a nuclear reactor for instance
– are regulating and stimulating, our negative synergies rear their heads
here again.
Here again it is not a case
of switching to humanist consequences. Yet, seeing the influence that the
distinction between matter and form has had in philosophy and ancient rhetoric,
seeing its role in the conception of nature as a permanent substrate and as man
as simple modeller of things, we glimpse, once again at the cultural transformation
implicated in the new motor schemes.
This too brief overview of
energetic synergies shows where their interest lies rather well. They do not
necessarily promise a decrease of the organs. The latter, in a Diesel engine or
a triode, are more plentiful than in the most abstract and corresponding
machines. Nor do they promise us that machines will be easier to understand or
easier to repair, or even more polyvalent. The abstract machine, insofar as it
separated the functions, was appropriate to the explanation. It was easily
repairable and was apt to a wide variety of roles. But the concrete machine
introduces a new world that, in its whole, is more powerful and flexible than
the former.
From the viewpoint that
concerns us, it particularly brings about a new mentality. There will probably
always be a vast number – if not a majority – of static (there is
no technical world without a hammer or a hoist) or dynamic (we will continue to
juxtapose functions for economic, convenience or prestige reasons, as we can
see in automobile accessories) tools and machines. There is probably no rupture
between the most abstract machines of the 19th century and our more
concrete machines, and the technical intention always encompassed a tendency to
concretisation. Still, probably in the same way today as yesterday, every
machine-related series must go through the most abstract, analytical stages, as
we can see with the present nuclear related researches. But globally speaking, the technical world
offers a new face. An increasing number of objects show a concreteness that is
so stunning that the technician can perceive it as such, so that he may pursue
it in an explicit manner, that from the point where he has to go back to
abstract stages – like for his new series – he knows that this it
what he tends to: this is the reason why he reaches it so quickly.
As we have just seen,
synergy, taken in all its extension, is synonymous with organic relations
between machine-related parts. It suggests dialectic relationships between machine
and nature, matter and form. Hence, we shall not be surprised that the recent
machine should introduce a new technical [47]
and cultural view of things, or that it should favour
it anyway. This is something that we shall verify in our information machines.
1C2. The dialectic machine of information
Let us not linger over
transmission machines such as the telephone, the radio, or television. All of
these, in what concerns their informational aspect, only aim at multiplying or
broadcasting messages. Their dynamist signification depends on the type of
network in which they fall. There is even less to be said for some calculators,
these arithmetic electrified machines that only add new commands to mechanisms
whose principle goes back to Pascal.
Yet, among our calculating
machines, some, more original, not only allow calculating but also allow
resolving problems. Analogical machines are devices that mime the data via
relations between physical forces. For instance, the tensions and resistances
of a circuit are adapted in such a way that they represent an equation whose
intensity of the current – when read on an ampere meter – provides the
result. We can see that the process, instead of being simply linear as in
arithmetic machines, exploits a complete structure. More remarkable still are
computers, which are capable of reaching their complex solutions numerically,
meaning through a succession of discreet quantities that are exactly
determinable. These logic machines [48]
adapt to the situation, confronting partial results obtained
using their instructions. They test a path, abandon it if it is not fruitful,
or chose another on the basis of anterior results that they either extrapolated
or interpolated in a sort of induction. Indeed, they can contain machines that
statistically induce averages, establish correlations, define laws of series
that they then interpolate and extrapolate. Where analogical machines exploited
a global structure more massively still – static or dynamist, as we wish
– the logical machine, with its permanent and transitory memories, also
interconnects every part of its system in a truly circular and already
dialectical manner from which a rectifying return to the past is never
excluded.
Our behavioural machines go
all the way down that road. Not satisfied with elaborating information that
they passively receive and return, they conjoin with their logic organs that
elaborate the information to deduct an appropriate directive, energetic organs
or execution and exploration, allowing them to complete tasks and harvest data
in a circuit of actions and reactions where we find three of the synergic forms
of insertion of a living in its milieu. Indeed, the living must ensure its
internal balance, whatever the information (more or less disturbing) that he
receives from the outside. He must explore his environment for new information.
He must be capable of learning (meaning sorting) amongst the information he
receives, which piece of information will be significant to him: the Pavlovian
conditioning is this complex operation through which an animal distinguishes,
amongst innumerable neutral stimuli, what announces a specific stimuli (such as
the prey or sexual partner) and has a signalling value.
Yet, the Ashby haemostat
that Grey Walter pictorially called the Machina sopora, is a machine made up of four
moving magnet galvanometers interconnected in such a way [49] that, should the
experimenter perturb one of the elements (for instance by blocking the needle),
the others would find their balance back because their main feedback is –
according to necessities – liberated or contradicted by secondary
feedbacks that are inter-composed in turn if one of them should be faulty. The
device is therefore homeostatic in relation to its milieu, which is represented
by a malevolent experimenter. Machina speculatrix, equipped with a photoelectric cell
coupled with a positive tropism and an electric contact coupled to a negative
tropism combines the data it hence receives so well that it launches into an
in-depth exploration of its vital space, avoiding some obstacle while moving
others, seeking the optimal (average) 'living conditions', recharges if need
be, adopts a differentiated behaviour in relation to its congeners, as with its
own image in a mirror. The Machina docilis, through its exploration mechanisms
(scanning), has thresholds of memory and perception that only grasp and retain
neutral stimuli that are effectively linked to specific stimuli. It is capable
of extracting 'significations' from its entourage, and to modify itself and
modify it in consequence. The behavioural machine is capable of extending to
its milieu the circularities that the logical machines conducted within itself.
We do not have to decide
whether we should apply the epithet of cybernetic to all these machines without
distinction, cybernetic identifier or information theory, or if we should
solely keep the term for behavioural machines. Nor do we do not have to decide
if, amongst the latter, the faraway future belongs to servo-mechanisms rather
than to their taping, predisposing them to tasks of control – as Wiener [50],
envisages – or if, at the opposite of these inventive
behaviours machines that stimulated Grey Walter's [51] reflection. Finally, we do not have to decide if the
properties of these engines wear out what is concrete in the behaviour of the
living, not even if every learning process (as Grey Walter requires after
Pavlov) is of an associative [52] nature. All these precisions are delicate and important in
themselves and go way beyond our intention.
Such as we have just
described them, and should they represent a more speculative than practical
interest, our information machines testify of the same synergies between organs
and functions, between machine and nature, between matter and form than our
energetic machines. Machina docilis alone demonstrates some that are positive and
negative and first and second degrees. This is why they stand out less through
the number of their elements than by the richness of their interconnection [53]. They are the place of blockages by informational conflicts,
of releasing through respite or reorganising jerks. Their action presents
'degrees of liberty' in the sense that they can accomplish a behaviour that is
foreseen as they follow different paths, and sometimes even to manifest types of behaviours that are unforeseen
or ignored even by their manufacturer. One single nuance separates energetic
machines from the information machines For the synergies that we have
recognised until now: the former illustrate best the intimacy of the
functioning, whilst the second illustrates the homeostasis and the creativity
of the behaviour. The conjunction of the two aspects is what differentiates
– for the time being – the living from the machine [54].
We can say that, in the
same way as the 19th century invented energy, the 20th
century invented information, which is as old as our world. It has been there
since an animal shook another using a sign, since some sort of mechanism
'commanded' another by a transmission. Furthermore, thanks to the telegraph and
the telephone, it took on such a considerable importance in the 19th
century that time increasingly became the fourth dimension of the
machine-related world. But never before the era when cybernetic was defined
– and despite the use of the regulator by Watt and its analysis by
Maxwell – had we so clearly perceived the originality of temporary models:
the possibility of the feedback where the effect acts on the cause either to
moderate it in homeostasis or to significantly confront a present with a past
in the creativity of learning. In effect, with the 'feedback' (the Germans
translate feedback par Rückmeldung) mechanisation joined synergy in time to synergy in space.
And, as always, the extreme
case made us conscious of a category that was still unclear. The explicit
discovery of the feedback led to the discovery of information in general.
Around the Second World War, engineers, physiologists, psychologists and
sociologists realised that with or without feedback information was a universal
truth whose common laws linked the machine, the living, the culture and the
milieu [55]. At the same time as this discovery, information in general
engendered the discovery of order as a reality that was complementary yet
distinct from energy [56]. Once again, we glimpse at the humanist consequences. The
machine no longer belongs to the area of raw force to manifest a reality that
is already spiritual and cultural: synergy not only in space but in time too.
However, we had promised
ourselves more than the application of the above-envisaged synergies, even more
than their extension in time. We had announced that our information machines
would offer us new synergies that, without being limited to these synergies,
would be illustrated more clearly.
1C2a. Synergy of the machine and the machine
At first sight, the
concrete machine enhances the characteristic of independence that already
frightened Butler in its abstract ancestors. The intimacy of the exchanges of
energy joined with the capacities of self-regulation and initiative allows it
to increasingly suffice to itself. A submarine rocket, with its long-term
nuclear reserve, its automatic search control and the rich versatility of its
internal and external structure, is the best example summarising this autarky
characterised by the magical word automation. The future of the machine would
then be the robot, the outcome of the 18th century automaton. It is
particularly fascinating and worrying, even sacred, that it clams up even more…
But this reminder of the 18th
century warns us of our error. The Swiss clockmakers' mechanical harpsichord
players and the eating, digesting, excreting duck created by Vaucanson all
showed a need for a game and fair exhibition (we will never stress enough the
playfulness of ancient mechanic, whose peak is in the work of Da Vinci) when
they did not unconsciously target promethean and demiurgic aims (let us recall
the Faustian aspect of the same Leonardo) [57]. It took a minister of finances to appoint Vaucanson
as inspector for silk manufactures for the man to invent, in 1741, the looming
machine that Jacquard will later perfect. Today's concrete technique is very
different. It does not look for game or performance, and it does not aim to
illustrate its machines through their independence, quite to the contrary.
Indeed, by definition
concreteness tends to encompass ever-vaster wholes. It only finds its energetic
accomplishment by overlapping the internal organs of a machine, even its
associated milieu, to associate them to others prolonging them in a
machine-related associated milieu. From the informational viewpoint, it is even
more synergic that it opens onto evermore numerous and varied circuit. This is
why the significant models of current automation are not the fair's robots,
these isolated workers, but the electric plants in Russia and America where the
most diverse engines tie in infinite relations of energy and information, right
to the furthermost unities so vast that they encompass both the landscape and
the road system. More than autarky, the ideal of our machines is versatility,
the possibility of inclusion in every varied machine-related situations.
This is not without raising
a delicate problem. Synergies of inclusion suppose that the machine should
remain a non-saturated, opened system. Yet, these internal synergies tend to
render it independent, making it a saturated system. Therefore, the current
machine cannot be versatile in the sense of the old tool, by simple lack of
differentiation [58]. Its opening must be linked to its distinction itself, in
the same way as these highly specified numeric machine that, according to their
coding, carry out extractions of cubic root or language translations. In a
word, we cannot absolutely say that our engines open or close. Insofar as they
accomplish themselves, they clam up to be pluggable, and the aim of their
synergies of independence is to enrich their synergies of inclusion. Even the
ultimate goal of the artificial satellite is not to float alone as long and as
far as possible, but to remain in contact with its base despite the distance,
and in the end, to be retrievable, as the recuperation closes the complete
circuit opposing it to the abstract linearity of dynamism. In a nutshell, the fundamental
technical concept is no longer the machine but the network [59], synergic whole of synergic machines.
The hence-understood
network offers a completely different physiognomy than that of former technical
establishment, particularly in what concerns the distribution of information.
During the era of the static machine, the equipment drew, transformed, and gave
back information on-site, or just about. Management roles (for instance the
political power of Rome during the Empire) were content with ensuring the whole
with some general conditions (money, road, safety) allowing specific
establishments to work. There was little to preoccupy oneself with
coordination. To the contrary, coordination became indispensable to the
dynamist machine because of its necessary concentrations of energy, and it
obtained it through the centralisation of resources and information. From one
viewpoint, we could say that it requires to be centralised. Everything depends
so much on everything that higher decisions suppose the confrontation of the
most information in one single point [60]. Yet, at the same time, secondary centres have such
originality that it is crucial to let them define the partial constellations in
every order amongst themselves. In such a way that the central power – if
we can call it that way – rather than being a centre for the broadcast
and the collection of information (and decision), plays a new role, that of a
facilitator (and activator) of interconnections [61]. We fall back upon analogies with life. But we particularly
feel the cultural, social and political transformations that this passage from
a pyramidal scheme (dynamist) to a plurinodal (reticular) scheme will require [62].
1C2b. Synergy of the machine and of man
Yet, the question surfaces
again. If the concrete machine opens to the network, does the latter not clam
up, evacuating man? To the contrary, the dialectic network comprises one last
synergy, and precisely with the human being.
We think of human
engineering, a
discipline that both concerns the engineer and the psychologists, and whose aim
it is, starting from an in-depth study of our organism and of the technical
object, to determine what structures the machine must present and what training
man must undertake for their coupling to be as profitable as possible. This
study goes all the way back to prehistory. Indeed, every tool has two sides:
one is turned towards nature while the other faces the worker. Taylor made this
study progress in the way that we know, attracting the interest of the wide
public. Yet, it did not have its current, decisive importance until the Second
World War during which ultra-rapid control devices (radars and cockpits)
required the most refined adaptations [63]. However, human engineering does not prove that the machine humanises
itself. It is probable that its theoreticians were led to give an increasingly
large share of the human factor in technical return, and as we saw, Taylor, starting
off from coercition, went to the gymnastic refinement of the gesture to finally
discover that the most stereotyped work presupposes satisfactions of ambiance,
contemplation, consideration, opening up, and joy [64]. Yet, these researches concern the human according to
something else. If things were to stay still, he would alienate himself.
Hence, to grasp the true
coupling of man with the technical object, we should compare them and see how
the concrete machine, insofar as it comes closer to man, determines and helps
him cultivate his difference [65]. The machine records more, quicker and more faithfully (it
even has a tendency to record too much, and this is well-known by communication
engineers who are endlessly fighting background noise). Yet, however lacking in
intelligence the listener of a conference may be, he will retrieve get more out
of a seminar than listening to a Dictaphone (a logical machine), sometimes even
more than from a behavioural machine. The latter, although equipped with
degrees of freedom and sometimes with types of associations unforeseen by its
manufacturer, proves to be much less inventive than the brain, which is capable
(according to Grey Walter) of establishing significant relations 'between just
about anything and anything', particularly capable – in virtue of the
cellular intimacy of its processes – to gain the realization where its
activity is no longer simply 'framed' like that of a machine, but 'framing' [66]. In a word, if the cybernetic machine that explores a sector
of the real with superhuman speed and precision (the electronic tube works a
thousand times quicker than a neurone) is master in the order of answers to
expected-type questions, the brain maintains its control in the order of the
interrogation, the project, and the response to unexpected-type questions [67].
This is what causes its
productivity in small tasks. Control cybernetic machines will render immense
services for the manipulation of large volumes, such as car assembly lines or
electricity plants, but they will never replace the duster, the greengrocer,
the garage mechanic, or all the workers in charge of very restraint jobs that
are very differentiated and occasional. The orange picking machine, which could
be built, would not be profitable. We can confess, along with Wiener, that the
navvy following the bulldozer to scrape the corners is the gleaner of the
machine. But gleaning requires a more difficult machine than reaping. The human
brain is alone – along perhaps with the animal brain [68] – that is sufficiently plastic to accomplish these
tiny adaptations economically.
As for the most demanding
(that the new techniques precisely postulate and where the animal and
animalised man are out of the game), the human brain – in what is most
distinct about it – is required. Indeed, the network towards which we
tend, from the very fact that it presents itself as a tissue of spatial
temporal interrelations that are prodigiously complex and fecund but fragile
too, and where the tiniest flaw entails long-term deviancies, supposes, just to
maintain itself, the continuous vigilance of the mind. But above all, like
Simondon remarked, its concreteness takes it into an endless process of
concretisation that, because of synergy, can only occur through global
reorganisations of every single one of its elements, meaning in a veritable
invention. The more concrete the object, the least it can evolve through the
improvement of the detail. It supposes that, with each major progress, a
complete revision of the entire system [69].
Ainsi, le réseau concret, tant dans son existence que dans sa genè. Hence, the concrete network, both in its existence and in
its genesis, forms – with the human brain – a couple where it is
concerned by what defines it: its interrogative and initiating capacity.
Evidently, this couple draws synergies that are not only of the first but also
of the second degree, where each term perfects itself as it perfects the other.
* * *
Throughout this entire
chapter, apart from a few rare exceptions, we limited ourselves to machines.
Was this justified if our ambition was to embrace every aspect of the technique
in general? Mumford used to remark that machines are a modest part of the
technical world that still encompasses tools (gripper), machine-tools (potters
wheel), utensils (jars), devices (oven), vehicles (cart, ships, aircrafts),
utilities (roads, rivers, canal locks, aqueducts), and even, beyond these
objects that extent into space, the processes that develop in time, such as
cookery, tanning, milling, weaving, dyeing, stock farming, domestication, right
to the synthesis of plastics or amino acids, without even considering today's
electronic and nuclear reactions. All this, to which we can also add the
transformation of the landscape introduced by agriculture and communication,
along with monetary manipulation, political or educational organisation,
belongs to the technique. All this exerts an undeniable cultural influence.
However, Marx was not wrong in thinking that here, machines are the most
striking and the most symptomatic element, at least since the 19th
century. Mumford himself seems to admit this when he adopts the convention of
speaking of the machines
in its own sense, and to designate the technical world in general as the machine.
And, indeed, the tripartite
division suggested by the fully machine-related domain can be so easily and
clearly found in all other forms of technique that it would be fastidious to
insist. Let us use the evolution of productivity as single proof. In every
order, the static era – in continuity with nature – aimed at
producing energies that were reduced but that were also waste-less. The artisan
excels at using every wood shaving, and nothing is neater or more economically
charming than the hydraulic and aeolian enforcement of the Dutch landscape in
the 17th century. At the opposite, the dynamic era, obsessed with
the quantities it produced, only granted a mediocre attention to wasted
quantities. Sometimes, symbolising power, it even boasted about it. Noise, smokes and mine dumps
are as flattering for a paleothechnical mining site than its extraction wells.
The concrete era, preoccupied with productivity, strives just about everywhere
– and particularly in its combustibles – to replace the diagram raw
matter = product + waste with the diagram raw matter = sub-product + sub-product [70]. In the case of
atomic energy, where waste is particularly toxic, it is even forced to do this.
The recuperation, the synergy of simultaneous and successive actions, is as
sensitive is our chemical processes than it is in the machines in the strictest
sense.
This is also the case for
political economy, an area where we move away from yesterday's simple activism.
To us, the industrialisation of a region is something completely different from
a gathering of capitals, a standardisation of processes, the transporting of
cheap raw material and the dispatching of excellent technicians. Here again,
the concrete network not only comprises the natural resources of a country, its
road network and raw human potential, but also its social organisation, the psychological
well-being of its workforce with its needs for stability and evasion, all in
circular causality, in such a way that the economic invention, just like the
machine-related invention, no longer consists in a local, quantitative
improvement, but in the creation of global forms where all the factors are
reorganised by transforming their reciprocal causalities [71]. This is why contemporary economy goes beyond the
dynamist-type centralisation and the artisan-type decentralisation. Its
founding concepts are no longer concentration or dispersion, but
inter-dependence [72], integration, complementarily, internal regulation, and
reorganising mobility. Hence, the corporatism of the static era and the
paleotechnical alternative of liberalism and dirigisme are all disqualified.
Through their underlying concrete structures, and insofar as they are more
developed, our capitalist societies seem stuck to a liberalism that is
increasingly planned – in the same way as our socialist societies –
to an increasingly opened dirigisme. Here, our goal is not to decide of the
future of these two systems, but, insofar as they are viable, they will not
just be a simple compromise, a good balance between centralisation and
decentralisation, but they will be an original reality responding to a new
concept of synergic economy that does not privilege the centre or the extremes
but includes them in its interactions.
And as the
same scheme of thoughts can be found in our medical planning, even in our
opinion surveys – which are all impregnated with abstract energetic
– it is indeed technique as a whole that has crossed three states:
static, dynamic, and dialectic.
Chapter 2 - THE HUMANIST SUGGESTIONS OF THE DIALECTIC MACHINE
The dynamic machine will
have taught us that we cannot be content with easy arguments to culturally
justify a technique. It is not enough to argue one's power to broadcast ideas,
to facilitate work, to increase leisure, or to suppress rarity. All this has a
price and makes it a means of culture. The latter is of creative essence and is
always compromised at least as much as any sort of means assists it. Simple
broadcasting and facilitating means can contribute to keep a moribund past
going.
Now we need to see whether
current technique is not itself (apart from being a means) a cultural reality
charged with values susceptible of a new departure in its structure and in its
modes of being and appearing. What requirements must it fill to this effect
apart from the three conditions of any principle of humanism: unveiling a
fundamental aspect of nature; engaging a new and essential conception of the mind; and implicating a motor restructuring of society?
2A. ARTIFICIAL NATURE
The ancient humanists were
supported from all parts by the idea of nature, the natural, and the nature of
things. It is all too clear for post-renaissance Greece and Europe, but the
same applies to all other epochs and under every latitude. If the Medieval, the
Byzantine, the Egyptian, the Chinese, the Indian, the African do not share the
preoccupations of the Greeks and the men of the Renaissance with reproducing
exterior forms and studying quantitative relations, it is not because they
despised nature in any way, but because they conceive it differently. The
Byzantine icons manifest Transcendence because the latter is the true
naturality for the orthodox. Hence, by agreeing on words, yesteryear's
humanisms were all realistic. In their eyes, truth, goodness and beauty all
stand before man, who only needs to recognise them. They can be conceived very
differently by Aristotelian empiricism that pursues them in sensitive facts, or
still, by the platonic or Cartesian rationalism that sees them in a world of
spiritual ideas. They can be immanent or transcendent. It does not matter. The
common factor between the idea and the fact is that they are data, that they
must be recognised. Hence the security of the traditional man: failing to act
like Parmenides or acting like Heraclites, he can be spotted from a distance
and is in a pre-established order [73].
The idealist mentality that
sees the light of day in the 18th century marks the first imperfection
of this beautiful, age-old construction. In every area, it insists on the initiative
of the subject, who knows, feels, and acts. For Rousseau, moral action is not
the accomplishment of a previous law, but it is measured by the lived intimacy
of the intention. For Hugo, beauty, instead of accomplishing the order, bursts
in the originality and the vitality of the creator. For Kant and Hegel, the
truth should not be abstracted or intuitive, but it proceeds from the mind that
makes up (if not create) the real. We should not dare say that idealism
completely breaks with the idea of nature: feeling for Rousseau, genius for
Hugo, mind for Kant and Hegel are realities that deploy an internal law and
that possess many of the characteristics of the already-there. However, a crack
appears, a defiance in relation to the given. It fuses with Kierkegaard,
explodes in a storm with Nietzsche, and will experience numerous echoes until
today, echoes that are mumbled or thundering in the thousands of varieties of
subjectivism. For example, and despite the paradox of terms, the end-of-century
naturalism will be one of the neatest questioning of objective reality. It is
no longer acribic in the detail, does not impatiently accumulate the tiny
notations, because for it, there are only fragments left, shards of nature,
meaning no more Nature at all [74].
Unanimously, the current
orientations inaugurate a third moment, offering to go simultaneously beyond
realism and idealism. As we shall see later, art learned with the masters no
longer believes in the ready-made objectivity of a nature that would only need
to be expressed. With the same strength, it refuses the simple cry of vain or
lame subjectivity, attempting to build a reality where man and nature would
conjugate. Science no longer confounds itself with a realistic acknowledgement
or an idealistic diktat to discover a system halfway between mind and nature.
Ethic no longer dares present itself as a code of prescriptions nor as the
romantic legitimation of anarchising fantasy: in its Marxist form, it ties a
living experience where mind and nature never cease to dialogue and weave a
reality that crosses fact and reality.
These three milestones of
civilisations vis-à-vis nature are evidently parallel to the three steps that
we already recognised in the history of technique. The static machine in
continuity with the human body and its milieu harmonised itself with a
conception of things where man could ask the real whether he was sensitive,
intelligent, fluent, stable, immanent, transcendent, but where he only thought
of conforming to it in a realistic attitude. The dynamic machine, breaking away
from the environment and appearing, or so we thought, of a calculation of the
mind, fitted in well with the sovereign affirmation of constructive
intelligence, which found its representatives in Hamelin, Whitehead or
Brunschvicg until the eve of the second world war. As for the concrete machine,
adorned with synergies between it and its milieu, between its matter and its
form, it is in full agreement with a representation of the world where forces
of nature and initiatives of the mind conjugate into an intermediary reality.
Indeed, what image of
things does it offer? The network tends to cover up the universe, closely
interconnecting the various machines, urban centres, road systems, railways,
rivers, air routes, Hertzian waves, and even industrialised agriculture. The
network invades the desert and the poles set up by a semi-artificial
agriculture, industrialised by solar ovens or by the easily transportable
atomic energy, used as the platforms for every sort of flight, included in
diverse radar and transmission relays. The network joins the oceans, about
which yesterday's speculations on tides, the resources of plankton and the
redistribution of maritime currents through a recasting of straights and
isthmus are constantly renewed. Finally, thanks to artificial satellites, the
cosmic space in turn enters the circuit, so much though the setting up of
spatial routes than by the anticipated changes of the high atmosphere,
improving the cycle of seasons and the resonance ceiling of our
telecommunication systems. We can see that the net is universal. It is tightly
knitted, particularly as it does not result from a simple accumulation of
engines and processes (as with the 19th century machine) but forms a
real fabric where each element continuously sends back to all the others,
stopping the glance on the endless relations of their interactions, and
stopping them from going beyond: virgin land.
Yet, we must note that this
screen is not satisfied with covering just the surface but operates an in-depth
coverage. It is the garment that annexes what it covers. Already, the
associated milieu had seemed to us to be so intimately united to the regime of
some energy and information machines that we could not decide if it was nature
or the machine itself. Simondon calls it techno-geographical. But the fusion of
the technique and the landscape is particularly sensitive in the great projects
of climatic transformation. Defying purely artificial processes of a linear and
abstract type, such as the emission of silver iodine at high altitude, we
envisage global adjustments where the introduction of a culture would change
the rain rate, hence favouring a new culture which would in turn reform the
rain rate in a cycle where nature would not be sovereign nor isolated but
inserted in a functional scheme in the manner of an organ or a moment [75]. Similarly, in food production, we no longer have the
submission of the ancient man who waited for his provender from the good will
of the elements, nor Berthelot's dynamist inflexibility that saw us eating
pills combined by chemical synthesis. We know that nature will always work more
economically for food production than we ever will [76]. If we do not envisage making a very nourishing alga, the
Chlorella, we have learned to cultivate it in transparent tube where it enjoys
solar light and optimal quantities of nitrogen and carbon in a semi-artificial
semi-natural mechanism where nature is, once again, annexed as an organ and as
a moment.
Finally, it is not solely a
question of annexation, but of true incorporation. Let us recall the synergy of
the matter and the form in the dialectic machine. Let us particularly put forth
the vastest example and the most startling of agricultural conceptions. The
soil, for the static mentality, was indeed a matter to which the human being
gave a certain imprint of his initiative, a form, but whose virtue he had to
respect. By reaction, the dynamist artificialism meditated to do completely
without it (Berthelot waited for the cultivated fields to stop disfiguring the
countryside), or to make it into a pure receptacle, a neutral place where the
vegetal would be put in contact with the products that we would have placed for
its industrial growth. The dialectic mentality envisages an almost absolute
co-penetration of the human and natural poles. It begins by recognising the
originality of the soil, whose texture, far from being neutral, stimulates the
chemical exchanges between the plant and the fertilizer, but uses it as it
wishes, penetrating this texture with such substances as the Kryllium that put
its very materiality in form. And we would dig deep into our synthetic products
– fabrics, materials, and food – for one thousand similar cases of
incorporations. It does not matter that a certain number of the examples put
forth are less results than projects: they outline a future that is so near
that they are already part of the world that we see and feel. And indeed, what
matters here – let us underline it for every analysis that will follow
– is less the face that nature has taken physically than the face it
receives, in our minds, of the new mentality. It matters little that more than
one invoked technique should be outdated: everything in the synergic world is
so changing that the Kryllium and the Chlorella will probably not dominate
tomorrow's agriculture. But they will make place to processes where the
universe and the human initiative will be even more closely confounded.
In a word, the technical
world, as it naturalises itself, henceforth makes nature technical by covering
it with its extension, by annexing it as an organ and as a moment, by
transmuting its very matter in its substance. It is no longer a third reign between man and nature, a metacosm according to Dessauer [77]because it does not join the two others by letting them
intact. It is more of a new unique reign that includes, that crosses the two
others, substituting them by putting them into relations that reinterpret them,
what we have called an improper name, improper because it does not express this
unity, a median reality [78]. At the border of concreteness,
there is no nature; there is no artifice, but an original, moving synthesis
that we can also call an artificial nature or a natural artifice. If the
urbanism of the future has 'silence areas' in store for us, and 'green bands',
it will be, there again, in a view to network nature: there, it will function.
We see how superficial it
would be to justify or criticise our technique by envisaging it as a means.
When a reality takes on such invading dimensions, when it fills the sensitive
world so well, in most cases it veils and even replaces every other truth, is
it still a means? A landscape is not a means; it is the milieu [79], the world-around-us, the Umwelt. The concrete technique does not
represent an intermediary, a medium that would stand between us and our goals
beyond. Most of the time, it is the goal of our actions itself, and our actions
end there. Every technical object taken alone evidently offers the means of an
action of another object, but the network is the very world in which we are
agitated or where we rest. And as it extends indefinitely into space through
its synergies, and, using the process of concreteness, into time, the concrete
technique not only forms our landscape, our Umwelt, but our horizon itself.
This affirmation is of an
incalculable cultural consequence. Nature – Earth, Mother Earth, Demeter,
Cybil, Isis, Physis, Thalassa, Desert, River, and Mountain – with its
thousand other faces, has been the fundament of man's values since his very
origins. The source of life, the maternal breast, blazing fire or fecund heat,
flood and rise in water level, drought and beneficial rain, silt or loess, it
had been even more fascinating and redoubtable, more sacred, that despotically
it gave seven years of meagre cows for seven years of fat cows, as it sowed
epidemics with one hand and healing with the other. It conveyed all the poetry,
the visual arts, the rhetoric, the philosophies, and the liturgies, in a word,
every humanism. When, after millennium of realisms, some forms of idealisms
wished to underline the primacy of the mind, it remained present as either root
or regret. The dynamic era of the machine could do nothing about it. By
refusing it, it only served to exasperate the sentiment of every man of
culture: Péguy could be left to his dreams of 'dying for the four corners of
earth', for a 'carnal earth'.
As we have already said,
our aim is not to sketch tomorrow's humanism. However, we must foresee that its
poetry, plastic, rhetoric, philosophy and liturgy [80] will no longer
play wallflower on old nature. In their images, they will no longer be able to
invoke it as a horizon, if it is true that concrete technique is our horizon.
But in no case will they be able to hide in the haughty interiority where they
have found refuge during the idealistic transition: seeing the expansion that
it supposes, a humanism never build itself on subjectivity, no matter how
refined or moving.
Indeed, whatever we may do,
the fecund cultural themes will be within the plan of this median reality where
the new technical mentality imprisons us. Is this a wide enough field, one that
is sufficiently deep in view of the former nature, to feed the untiring need for
the renewal, for the creation of humanism? It seems so, because this reality is
coextensive with the old mentality, even brining it new dimensions. If the
technique did not go beyond its status of means, offering it as a horizon would
obviously condemn us to the nonsense of a world where everything would only be
the means-of-means. However, by merging with nature to create a median reality,
landscape and horizon, concrete technique ceases to be a servant to become a
cultural becoming in its being. Involving nature in its synergic totalities, it
does not only present utilities but forms, in the Goethe sense of what does not exhaust
oneself in being sent back to something else, but offers a sense by itself, in
its completeness.
2B. THE INSTITUTOR MIND
The idea of nature was so
strong in ancient cultures that the mind was conceived on its model. When
Descartes saw the soul as being a thinking thing faced to the extent, he was
only speaking good sense, the good sense of every literate or illiterate man of
his era. Seeing the visible and exterior nature, the mind was invisible and
interior, consistent and sufficient. Its relations with the world had the ease
of the rider on a horse, to use Plato's popular image.
We could think that ancient
technique did not legitimise such views. The coarseness of casting processes
and the fact that human, animal, hydraulic, an wind energies were passed
through coupling systems where every distance and bifurcation causes
considerable losses obliged the artisan to realise miracles of manual dexterity
and plastic invention that, far from rendering him pure, would force him to
seek ideas following very humble steps, through trial and error. 'Taking some
off here, adding some there', says Philo of Byzantium about his catapults. This
is how training was passed down from the master to his apprentice in those
days. Thereby, we should expect that the philosophies of the era saw man as a
whole of gestures through which a thought would search itself without ever
managing to possess itself completely. This was not the case. Did the division
of social classes mean that the philosopher could not be an artisan? In real
fact, the ancient machine suggested a superior conception to all. Its use,
manufacture and invention supposed very physical manipulations. However, once
its technical form was completed, it seemed so elementary and so obvious that
the mind could be under the illusion of having conceived it using the sole
resources of his intuition (whether intellectual or sensitive, it is irrelevant)
and his reasoning, independently from the gesture. The matter seemed a stubborn
receptacle for the form and the gesture a declining execution of the idea [81]. The free man was careful not to get his hands dirty. The
wise man looked for shelter in his mind, before or above things, because he was
himself a sufficient, thinking thing.
The coming of dynamism only
reinforced this distance. Breaking from empiricism, dynamism penetrated the
technique of science, again humiliating manipulation. In Watts' machine we find
the confluents of the researches of such researchers as Savery and Newcomen,
but also of theoreticians such a Galilei, Torricelli, Guericke. When, in 1794,
the Convention founds the first polytechnic school, the great Carnot and Monge
call upon the inheritors of the saeculum matheematicum, Lagrange, Laplace, Legendre, and
Fourrier. Thermodynamic, inaugurated by Sadi Carnot in 1824, will bring the
idea that every thermal machine is reduced to the projection of a general
theory. And this feeling will find confirmation in the increasingly numerous
applications of chemistry and electricity (particularly since 1850) where it is
difficult to differentiate what results from the physician from the technician.
It is true that a plethora of German technicians reacted against this
assimilation, triggering a general consciousness that led to – in 1875
– the foundation of the Munich Laboratory of experimental Technology.
However, for the public at large and for most authors, technique continued to
play its role of applied science. And it could have been any different. These
still-abstract engines where each function was made on its own were presented
as a stack of successively incarnated physical laws. More than ever, the mind
felt independent from the exterior manipulations of the conception of technical
structures. Were the latter not the simple applications of truths that had been
discovered through reasoning and intuition, sensible for empirics, intelligible
for idealism, and whose systems pave the entire period? From the gesture, the
exploring manipulation, technique considered as vulgar, the only residue was
problems of execution to which
science had not yet brought all its theoretical limpidity.
Concrete technique modified
this state of things in-depth. In the presence of our engines and processes,
the mind cannot have the illusion that manipulation and execution are
indifferent and that the only things that matter are acts of intuition and
reasoning, for it is obvious that synergy only occurs through pure reasoning. A
ramjet, a Guimbal turbine, a pentode, a calculator or behaviour machine, a
recent economic or climatic plan present a global structure, a total structure
whose efficiency does not result from the successive action of elements, but of
their interaction. The understanding of the object can then require, in certain
cases – if not by right, at least by fact – that it should be
completely finished. During the 1958 Brussels World Fair, the cover cladding
the French pavilion pulled at the facades instead of leaning on it. This was
only noted when the pavilion was completed. Grey Walter only noticed that the Machina
speculatrix had
unforeseen types of behaviour once the machine was at work. When we are not
made to wait for a finalised object, we must at least have models. The
architect equipped with formulas on the resistance of materials has never
calculated as much as today. Still, he never worked so much on a scale model
either. Indeed, the model alone allows him to define synergic structures such
as parabolic hyperbolic in the material construction or the free plan in the
spiritual conception of the building. This is even more the case when the
architect or the inventor of a turbine work without a scale model, only with
their drawing board. What happens then is that their work – insofar as it
is synergic – presents itself not as a simple inscription of physical
laws, but as a living, testing, manipulating research of a spatial, plastic
configuration. And should they be required to leave for an instant the rulers
and tracing to continue their meditation in an armchair, it is still a
manipulation. The dialogue between the project and the object can become as
mental as we want; the mind that defines a concrete technique is not conceived
as a ruling reality that is solely intuitive and analytical. It is a labouring
principle that finds its way through gestures that are sometimes imagined,
often testing or winning, until the whole of the data achieves – either
at once or in different steps – a new form, a new balance, one that is
more comprehensible than the old one.
Clever minds seem to lodge
a challenge against this theory. The current age would be characterised by the
absorption of technique into science, and nothing is more stupid that the
policy of patents protecting the inventors of engines, hence neglecting the
inventors of ideas that are usually more fecund. The reign of the plastician
and the manipulator, linked to the deficiencies of the ancient machine, would
be over. And, if we need to establish a circuit, 'it is better to make a
skilful application of static principles and of the calculus of variations to
find the best possible circuit, than to work by trial and error'[82]. Yet, talking in this way first implies that we leave the
best part to the information machines; these nerves of a network that will
continue to count its muscles, the energy machines, where the effort of
configuration is obvious [83]. On the other hand, the act of configuration is primary, even
for information machines. A circuit is neither a machine nor a machine-related
system; it is an aspect, a cut on the object whose complete idea is the
implementation of a situation where the spatial-temporal test (as pure as it
can possibly be) leads the game. Consequently, if it is true that the technique
is increasingly penetrated by science, if its leaps forwards are tightly
conditioned by the progresses of fundamental research, if the policy of patents
and subsidies should be led towards long-term researches, science and technique
are still very distinct from one another. Indeed, where one discovers laws, the
other configures objects in situation that enforce these laws without being reduced
to them. Therefore, nothing is more false than believing that the idea of
creative manipulation belongs to the imperfections of primitive technique. To
the contrary, since it is no longer mixed up with sweat, it appears to be
linked to the institutor exercise of the mind, searching for its projects and
ideas through more or less vague gestures. Finally, as we shall explore in the
second part, we should not forget that science (which is close to concrete
technique) is no longer 19th century science where it worked through
intuition and reasoning and envisaged the mind independently from corporal
steps, but it is a science that has – in turn – become dialectic,
realising that it also implied manipulation.
And, once again, a
character put in relief on a concluded case is universal. Having found
ourselves to be labourers in the edification of the concrete machine related
schemes, we realised that this had always been our role in the eotechnical and
the paleotechnical, even if the ease of the era could have fooled us. Every
technical instrument (as simple as it may be) is the fruit of an act of
configuration [84] – more or less stereotyped or creator, or still,
institutor depending on the situation [85] – that
differs from the discovery and the application of a law, and supposes a
spatial-temporal manipulation (that is direct then indirect) of the elements in
situation. We saw more clearly than the artist (the other disinterested [86] institutor who had also started off from the gesture, from
the chisel of the sculptor to the first word of the poet) and we realised that
what we call an idea is only a vague project filling and determining an
execution that Delacroix referred to as creative. Finally, psychologists and
sociologists demonstrated that we proceeded in the same operative – we do
not use the word empiric – manner when we build our laws and morals. Of
course, it is not a question of insisting that concrete technique alone
discovered the status of the mind labourer – we shall see that science,
ethic, and art reached the same result, each in their own field – but it
is possibly the most striking illustration, hence the most efficient
culturally. In any case, this illustration is no stranger to the fact that
every current philosophy and psychology repeats that we grasp within and on
things, in and on our steps towards them. Thought is not a sufficient and
initial phenomenon, it is a reprise that is constantly renewed and threatened,
of a within on an outside.
Here again, we have nothing
to recommend, but it seems obvious that in the future, it will be very
difficult to conceive humanism – as all ancient cultures had done –
in the manner of a retirement into the isolation of the creative mind. The only
way that the thought can grasp itself does indeed seem to be if it turns itself
towards these things to which it is now tributary in such a way that its
contemplation will not consist so much in an autarkic silence than in the
attentive deciphering of appearances and the operating engagement. This even
seems to be its unique chance for true interiority. But is it not its death and
that of all humanism?
In the vast area of culture
(as we are solely focusing on the techniques), we must not forget that the new
things towards which the thought moves are not dead objects or the
means-of-means. They are a median reality where it finds its own realised
structures, prolonging it and coming back to it to stimulate itself. Is a
concrete technical form – through the intimacy of it is interrelation and
the global reorganisations of its development, its crossing between nature and
intention – anything else than the thought appearing in front of itself
and receiving the most profound lessons? We had never clearly conceived that
our psychological structure was not additive, analytic, but that it was global.
The Psychology of the form is formed around 1912. We had never felt that our
freedom was not limited to a possibility of choices between ready-made
realities, but that it had the powers to remodel the real, to recast it, form
and matter, in truly novel structures. All the existential theories on the
introducer power of freedom begin between the two great wars. Never before
– before grasping itself as though forced to recuperate itself on the
object that it introduces – had the mind guessed that it was not itself
nature, but that it was a flaw, an emptiness-in-the-full through which movement
and history enter. Just before the Second World War, Sartre offered to envision
conscience as 'nothingness'. Here again, we cannot say that concrete technique
on its own provoked these statements: pure science, art and ethics all have
their original part. But technique gave them a face and showed them with a
force that implodes them popularly, transforming them into a cultural
blossoming.
In a word, everything
happened as though the mind had discovered that it was dependent on its works
as they had enough spirituality to reflect and stimulate these cerebral
assembling, these complex behaviours, and to simultaneously encourage its
behaviours to perceive its irreducible character of conscience, of distance on
all the data, its mean to promote them. Hence, it is not unthinkable that it
should contemplate at the very moment when it turns to the outside, by grasping
the outside like a within [87].
2C. CLASSLESS SOCIETY
Ancient technique favoured
the division of society in hostile classes. The static machine did not conquer
poverty as much as it underlined it by allowing access to luxury by a lucky
few. The dynamic machine put an end to rarity, triggering opposition between
businessmen, technicians and working livestock. This fracture was more severe
still because, if the old cleavage between the rich and the poor had something
natural about it that made it bearable, the new cleavage resulting of artifice
and the management of man by man seemed to be such a voluntary state that it
locked away the worker in tasks so inhuman amidst a general scheme of
humanisation that it was about to reinforce the fight of the classes everywhere
that the great industry was to take control.
To believe some
theoreticians, today's machine worsens this situation. It leads to the network,
and what characterises the network is that it is suspended to its control
centre. By destroying a power plant, a telephone or a television exchange, a
region is paralysed. By ruling over a radio or television emitter, an entire country
is broken up or galvanised. Russell [88] felt that the greatest danger of the future
was if a handful of left or right-winged adventurers were to take control of
the levers and, using an intermediary class of policemen that had been bought
with privileges, would exploit a servile humanity. He detected such dangers in
Hitlerism and Stalinist Communism.
Still, Russell understood
the network in a dynamist perspective. He saw it as a suite of initiatives
going off from a centre and of productions going back to a centre according to
a strictly linear process. Yet, the concrete network has many centres. Because
of synergy, elements are themselves secondary knots, and the secondary knots
are main knots. In such a way that the top – insofar as there is one –
has a relation of reciprocity with the base. By this, we do not wish to invoke
the commonplace that, in a society, everything is tributary from everything, in
the sense of Sully Prudhomme (where he would wonder about the mutual dependence
between the butcher and the prince, since this dependence is compatible with
the greatest of servitudes). We do not mean that this state of the machine
supposes a generalised qualification of the workforce, because in the linear
systems of dynamism we can also foresee qualifications (albeit mind numbing and
slaving), even when, beyond chain work, they rise up to intellectual tasks.
There is an intelligence that is used to enlist instead of awakening, as
national socialism proved in its day. But precisely, the interdependence and qualification
in the dialectic network cannot be limited to an execution that has become
sclerotic. As the objects to manipulate are synergic, an ever-growing number of
workers are forced to access a critical knowledge, one that is inventive and
that focuses on varied, wide wholes [89].
This is not a view of the
mind, and proving this is the insistency of economists on the urgency of a type
of training that (at each work position) should not be the narrow
specialisation where many technical schools are still confined or the old
general knowledge floating above or besides specialisations, but a training
that should direct everyone, through his own speciality, towards the whole
where it works, in such a way that the person can go beyond it sufficiently to
be apt to at least grasp the reorganisations of the whole. The democratisation
of studies that we are witnessing is not only a humanitarian measure (or else
it would not have successfully completed) but it is a necessity of the concrete
network. The latter supposes very high competences (we only need to think of
the great universities, such as Princeton) but also a very large pool of
comprehensive, inventive workforce, a need that goes so far that a certain
lowering of the level of studies to generalise its access has even been
suggested.
It follows that, contrary
to Russell's opinion, a society of utter exploitation is incompatible with a
developed, concrete technique. It is possible that a clique should take over a
synergic network and destroy it, but not that it should develop it or even
maintain it unless it progressively ceased to be a clique and favoured, against
all odds, emancipation and reciprocity. This is what Stalinist society
illustrates. The latter started off as a police dictatorship before moving
– using the very logic of the technique it instigated and that was
sliding from abstraction to concreteness – to a society where the
critical mind and values of reciprocity ended up (probably despite and against
the will of its promoters) demanding a more humane climate [90].
Anyway, concrete technique
corrodes every class. If by that we understand any group of individuals sharing
the same interests and defending them with some cleverness and pride, it goes
without saying that human societies will always comprise classes. Yet, the word
infers something else. It implies that the group in question opposes to the
others, that it feels that it is naturally inferior or superior, that it attributes
itself with an irreplaceable mission inscribed in the great scheme of things,
even if this mission – like the Marxist proletariat – is to
overthrow every partitioning. Yet, such a class – in the strong sense
– is endlessly demolished, crumbling from the inside by the concrete
machine. The latter gives place to a reciprocity and a reorganisation of function
showing their contingence and preventing their sacralization into classes. We
are witnessing a secularisation of the role. Until recently, a man was a
greengrocer, an intellectual, or a military; an aristocrat, a bourgeois, a
labourer; he lived in the city or was a peasant; he was a coloniser or was
colonised. He has some memories of that, but the world in which he lives, the
way in which he exerts his function increasingly forces him to only appear as a
man, only a man, in the eyes of others and his own. There is no place for the
stable aristocracies of the blood, money or investiture, but only for a general
semi-elite from which a fluent super-elite [91] emerges, in the most varied places and according to
extremely varied or momentary needs. Classes are endlessly re-forming, but they
are constantly coming undone too, sometimes ceasing to be classes [92]. And we could say the same for nations. There is a ferment
of unanimity in the dialectic network. Not only does the network force us to
conceive ever-vaster political and economic wholes, but also (against all odds)
it conjoins them increasingly narrowly [93]. Let us recognise that the thinning of the class does not
promise alone a cultural future. In the past, it was often a sign of fatigue,
and today we denounce the lifelessness of some American milieus encouraged by
the new technical mentality towards a lowering of the social barriers. However,
a book like William Whyte's The Organisation Man [94]
would tend to suggest optimism precisely through its
criticisms. The book testifies of the stagnation – but one that is
denounced, hence outdated – by an author and an audience. Concrete
technique – since it includes social issues as one of its factors –
propels it from within. A network built on the synergy of the machine and man
favours human relations whose consequences can be egalitarian, even oppressive, but its
necessities of invention force it – in the short term – to test
them as such and contradict them. To pastiche a Heidegger formula, tomorrow's
society will – by structure – endlessly question its structure
itself. If it seems capable of promising itself a creative future, it is not
because through ignoring unbalance, but because the latter (in virtue of the
needs of differentiation and of reorganisation of the concrete network) will
always be considered and undertaken.
2D. THE CONFIRMING LIMITATIONS
The above could lead us to
think that concrete technique answers the first criteria of a viable
civilisation: creativity [95]. But does it also satisfy to the second: self-regulation, or
the capacity to re-establish balance when it is compromised? It seems obvious,
as the object of a large number of our cybernetic structures is precisely
ensuring homeostasis, and as the feedback has become a concept that is as familiar to
economists and sociologists as to engineers. However, if we consider every one
of the implications of a concrete network, we find that it faces a double
threat from that point of view.
2D1. The difficult forecast
Old nature had its vices
but its advantages too. Its course, envisaged at large scale in both time and
space, was relatively self-regulating. With its simple laws of natural
selection, of adaptation to the milieu, of compensation via anti-bodies, it
always ended up returning health after plagues and the jungle after fires. Even
human psyche - whether cradled or shocked - alternated declines and
renaissances. At the opposite, if the synergic technique allows man (for the
first time in history) to dominate his destiny by creating an artificial
nature, if it governs the landscape, the conservation and propagation of the
specie, the education, the work and even the opinion – hence eliminating
the wrongful self-regulations at short term – it is not to say that it
should succeed brilliantly in the long term.
We should fear that
synergy, because of its very coherence, should lead to irreversible
deteriorations in certain areas. This is not likely in machines per say, where
a faulty programme can always be corrected. But it is the case for medicine
where the dietary artificiality, the use of antibiotics, the accrued radiations
could – in the long term – engender irreversible degeneracy. And it
can be particularly feared in our economic, social, and educational plans. The
global re-organisations of our exchange systems, opinion campaigns –
including those that favoured mental hygiene in Scandinavia, social conformism
in the USA, and bellicose in China – could very well overlap their
mechanisms of compensation seeing as their action is more concerted and
extended.
We should thereby be able
to forecast a long way away [96]. Yet, forecast is not easy in a synergic world because the
clear vision of a concrete scheme supposes that its conception, or even its
realisation is completed. To judge it, we must know the effect of each element
on all the others, on all of them on the milieu, and inversely. We can still
guess rather easily what a machine-related system is to become, for instance as
to the resistance of materials, because the object – or its scale model
– can be subject to tests (let us think of ventilating fans for scale models
of planes or architecture) drawing a sufficient outline of its future. Nothing
here prevents us from practicing a lesting to destruction that is rich in teachings. But the
task becomes more complicated in medicine where we must rely on thin
statistical prognostications to suppose the long-term effects of a radiation.
And we are practically helpless in everything related to psyches, where no
strict calculation, resistance or probability can help us. We are confronted to
a paradoxical situation. More than any technique, synergy forces us to foresee,
and its complexity prevents us from seeing where the forecast would be most
useful.
No argument will allow us
to exclude these pessimistic suppositions that require many restrictions.
Firstly, we must not attribute every catastrophe in the future to the idea of
synergy. Should western economy incur a great crisis one day, or even an
impasse, the fault would not systematically fall upon the synergic will that
increasingly animates it, but should fall upon the leftovers of a dynamist
mentality that proved itself in the great crisis of 1930.
Then, it is excessive to
think that forecast is impossible in an economical and psychological synergy. A
global functioning prefigures, if not in its parts, at least in the approached
totalities. On the other hand, despite its brisk returns, dialectic does not
systematically have to be consumed for us to know where it leads. Hence, there
is no need to despair that we are reducing the huge split separating our
forecast in human sciences from the previsions that we enjoy in the physic
techniques [97], particularly as we have shown an interest in these.
Finally, when we fear that
synergy should get carried away in a monstrous, exclusive direction, we all too
soon forget that it is not an idealistic construction and that the artificial
nature that it built still includes eternal nature in a dialectic relation. The
educator, the economist and the psychologist may plan insofar as their planning
is concrete and that it corrects itself through the naturalness it assumes. It
is in the diktats of dynamism that the cleavages could be definite rather than
being reduced to more or less unhappy development phases.
Hence, if we cannot exclude
the hypothesis of a severe, even fatal, disturbance in the psychological
factors of a synergic network, the only means of prevention lies in the
tightening and the extension of these synergies. The excesses of concreteness
call for concreteness. That this should make us happy or unhappy, its limits
confirm it.
2D2. Atomic violence
A second limitation of the
concrete network comes from its most elaborate product: the atomic weapon. The
latter is indeed a fruit. We can say that these engines converging the network
into a point where it self-destructs do not belong to the synergic mentality
and are hence not a sequel of dynamism; the fact remains that this new
technique is capable of combining the motor and informational synergies of an
anti-airplane post or an intercontinental missile. Furthermore, we can say that
it bears within itself the fabrication of engines of that type as a permanent
possibility and threat.
We cannot stress the peril
enough. It seems to lie in the fact, as Günther Anders [98] noted, that men
seem inapt to think it. The masses only reacted to this sporadically.
Politicians and military continue to speak and act as though they had
traditional weapons between their hands, albeit more powerful. Even pacifists,
who boast that they see the menace and want to share their clairvoyance,
usually express themselves in outdated categories where there are more good
sentiments than objective views.
This powerlessness is
hardly surprising. Our imagination and our sensitivity are not capable of
realising such a volume of destruction, of perceiving the monstrosity of an
action where there is no tangible proportion between the effect (the
catastrophe) and the cause (the turn of a key), where thousands of kilometres
separate the aggressor from its victim, where the victim itself (as we saw in
Hiroshima) does not feel to be the object of an aggression but rather of a
natural cataclysm where there is no more hatred, no more passion, no more heat
of the fight from the assailer or the assailed. In such a way that a being who
is incapable of harming a fly – or in any case of cutting the throat of
another human being – can demonstrate the technical serenity of a Truman
before and after Hiroshima. Both our morals and our laws fail us if we qualify
these means that no longer have an end, if not of the destruction of the means
and the ends. And our vocabulary cannot even designate the process. It can
provide us with the term war, which is improper, as we cannot speak of war when
the victim is without resistance, when it is highly probable that there is no
winner, or one that it so mutilated that he cannot recognise himself anymore.
We are, both intellectually and affectively, completely helpless before the
atomic weapon.
However, our engines of
destruction are becoming so powerful that it is not easy to draw the limit to
their territory, the information network between aggressors and defenders is
getting so narrow, and the responses between the camps are so instantaneous
that any atomic strategy seems to be deemed to failure both in time and space.
Our nuclear armament offers us increasingly terrifying catastrophes, albeit
increasingly improbable. We must hope that the impasses to which it leads will
trigger, in a more or less distant future, a quick jolt to political conscience
that will lay it to sleep forever.
In any event, and this is the conclusion that concerns our intention,
atomic rockets will change nothing to the current process of concreteness. They
can suppress it at any given moment, but they cannot slow or incurve its
course. The fact that man not only knows that he is perishable (something that
has always suited him), but that his culture and perhaps the entire humanity
are perishable at any moment seems beyond his capacity of representation to
give him a sentiment of a closed horizon, slowing down cultures and forecasting
decadence. No, that whether human defence versus atomic defence should move to
a plethoric armament or that it should force us – through a dialectic
come-back – to a general disarmament and a lowering of borders, its sole
cultural role – apart a possible destruction – will go to a reinforcement
of the synergy – machine-related in a first while and economic, political
and social in a second time.
We always come back to the
idea that concreteness feeds concreteness. So much so that the dialectic
schemes, with all the consequences that we recognised in the order of
artificial nature are alone in inscribing themselves in the lineage of the
reflected emergence of a culture.
* * *
profoundly shaped the time and space in which we evolve, its structures command
our gestures, thoughts, desires so intimately that it would not be impossible
to deduce – from these general characters – all the other domains
of our culture: of science, the art, and ethics.
But this way of doing could
present a danger. It is not because two cultural sectors present similar traits
that one has necessarily borrowed from the other, even if the other is more
visible. They were perhaps inspired in a reciprocal enlightenment, unless they
both arose from what we can call, along with the Kulturgeschichte, the spirit of the times, which has
not come out of nowhere. It is the result of accomplished works. By crossing
their influences, it elaborated an original synthesis of images, feelings,
wills that then turn back to the works to give them, in the most varied
sectors, some common traits. On the other hand, we must admit, with Marx, that
technical conditions fundamentally command a cultural moment. However, we
should add – as Marx does and as existentialist Marxism insists –
that super-structures are original that they spontaneously react on
infrastructures, and that they also count as the real causes (material, in
Marxist language) of the situation [99].
This is why we are now
going to discuss the humanist characters of our science, our art, our ethic, by
envisaging them for what they are without attempting to take them out of our
former analysis, even if we must encounter them at every turn.