It is necessary to gauge, one last time, to what extent
photography has continuously upset human conduct and behavior. In every
civilization, people have always been immersed in environments where mysteries
were perceived and were part of everyday life. To perceive means, as
phenomenology has long since described it, to be in a place for a duration of
time amongst objects and events disconnected from a background, according to
systems of orientation polarized by two eyes, two ears, two nostrils (on
both sides of the nasal bone, as Bower insists), two arms, two legs, a very
mobile head on an occipital spinal column, to which are added different
successive layers organized according to the degree of cerebral development
(perceptual, logical, semantic schemata), in addition to vast analogical and
digital sign systems that are culturally instituted. Perception as elective and
globalizing: per-capere. What then distinguishes oeuvres that are
considered important, those works that are called masterpieces in the arts and
crafts? The answer is straightforward: it is due to an intensification, a
surcharge of perceptual conditions. From the cave paintings to Cezanne, from
the Andean flutist to the Wagnerian orchestra, one can discern intensified and
surcharged perceptions that secondarily trigger conceptualizations. Through the
curvatures of the trait and the mark, through sonic torsions, through the
gathering in the (pictorial, sculptural, architectural, oratorical, choreographic)
frame-trap, through the coherence of (perceptual, motive, semiotic, and
sometimes indicial) field effects in particular, place is condensed into
ubiquity or multi-presence, while duration is condensed into eternity or Aevum.
Microcosms of the macrocosm. Accordingly, man and his oeuvre were concrete;
they had grown together (con-crescere). The Greek stage, where thousands
of citizens converged in semicircle while focusing on three actors and about
fifteen members of the chorus - all of them embraced by the gaze and hearing -
was one of the most exigent accomplishments of this perceptual pretension. Theatre,
a word derived from the Greek theasthai, means to embrace by the eye
(and the ear) from a fair and equitable distance.
One could say without much exaggeration that the photograph
frustrates nearly every property of perception. Of course, on a photographic
positive one can clearly perceive bright and obscure zones on white paper. In
this respect, the real and reality converge. In the encounter of photons and
halides, the real engenders the black spots while reality intimates that these
are indeed marks or zones. But this is not really what one thinks about when
speaking of photographs and how they are used. The reality that is envisioned
appertains more closely to the possible spectacle that these marks and areas
bring into view. As we have already noted, this spectacle-reality-there,
intensely consumed by the real (by virtue of carrier photons diversely
abstracted and filtered), sidetracks the perceptible and creates a kind of
non-scene through its superficiality of field, its matter-of-fact framing, its
relentless isomorphism and synchronism, its negative-positive alternations, its
ostensible digitality, its informational subcharge and surcharge, and its
monocular and cyclopean capture (while
paintings, although bidimensional, are binocular, which is surely the case with
Cézanne, but also even with Mondrian).
Thus, the most innocent gaze on a photograph creates a
decidedly uncanny situation. On the one hand, there is the viewer who sometimes
walks around in a gallery but who most often is seated and leafs through a
magazine, thus being in a situation of concrete perception. On the other one
hand, there is a sheet of darkened paper that is actually perceived, and which
signals a spectacle that defies almost all perceptual conditions while
displaying space, but by no means a place. Temporally speaking, things are even
stranger. The viewer is well and truly enveloped in a duration, and even in an
actual present, with a consistency characteristic of any present. And
the viewer is confronted with an object whose possible spectacle, for its part,
lacks all consistence of duration. It is even a provocative instance of pure simultaneity
as defined in physics: concomitance, at the speed of light, between the
emission of photons by the spectacle and their impregnation on the film, the
latter datable to a billionth of a second after the passage of the last photon.
In other words, all that concerns the viewer takes place in the present, in the
Bergsonian concrete simultaneity, while all that concerns the photographic
spectacle takes place in four-dimensional space-time, in Einsteinian abstract
simultaneity. And the historical debate between these two illustrious men shows
to what extent the dialogue was really a dialogue of the deaf.
Consequently, this process cannot really occur between
photographic imprints and the body, nor does it occur between signs and
imprints. So, where exactly do things happen? Simply put, everything takes
place between the print's bright and dark areas and our mental schemata.
To clarify this point, and also for historical reasons, it is
absolutely necessary to abandon the technical definition of the sign proffered
by Saussure, and to revisit the term in its common and traditional meaning
which holds that a sign is a complex of signals designating the designated, an event or an object.
Accordingly, one can distinguish six terms that describe this operation of signification.
Signification takes places between the poles of the sign or designated; an
object or event; interpretants, and other signs contrastive with the initial
sign, an addresser (sender) and an addressee, and finally - and this is the
point that interests us here - between the designant (désignant) and the
designated (désigné), a mental scheme. In the world of ancient
artisanship, which was dominated by signs and organized in a relatively stable
reality, the salient points of this operation were, apart from the sender and
addressee, the sign and its designated. We can clearly see that there was a
certain mental schematization at work that was so well wedged between and
aligned with the designated and the designant (désignant) that it
allowed one to speak in the singular using terms such as idea, concept, notion,
or representation. Thus, everything remained within the boundaries of a cosmos,
of a mundus.
Even the smallest of photographs upsets this security. The
photograph does not contain veritable designants (désignants) or signs,
nor does it contain a real designated or referent, and it therefore cannot have
interpretants (the photograph contains very little reality; it is hardly a
universe or microcosm). However, the photographic imprint is often a carrier of
indices, and possibly also indexed indices, and is therefore an extraordinary
trigger of a mental scheme. Or rather, one should say mental schemata.
Because precisely what these indices reveal is that, in their incessant
germination and overlap there are, at every instance, dozens, even hundreds of
mental schemata and not just one single scheme. In other words, this means that
ideas or concepts are semiotic illusions; they are acts of violence imposed by
the desire of reality to capture the ever elusive real. In effect, even in sign
systems, the unity of concepts or ideas cannot be but illusory. When I say
"sugar," whatever may be circulating between the sign and object is by no means
a simple thought but a crossroads where a host of notions may be activated:
substance, matter, sweet, powdery, in pieces, crystalline, fondant, sickening,
pleasant, bad for diabetes, carbon, sugar bread. In common discourse, speakers
incessantly tinker with thousands of mental schemata that spiral and come to
fruition, where metaphors and metonymies are not mere stylistic figures.
Instead, they must be seen as the fundamental functioning. That is precisely
what artificial intelligence has made apparent. To be able to use the
words "arc" or "to walk," artificial intelligence demands that we define them
and that we provide their concepts or ideas. Thus we get underway, believing
that a few well-chosen semantic traits would suffice. But three pages of
semantic traits will still not allow any A.I. to understand or to imagine what
we mean with the phrase "The triumphal arch tilts without threatening to
topple," or, more decisively in "Mark walks with difficulty," or simply "Mark
is walking." The designants (désignants) "arch" and "walk" attain their
designated only through multitudes of mental schemata, and this works
analogically rather than digitally (which is the only way of managing this
worrying plural). What artificial intelligence forces us to acknowledge in the
domain of signs, the photograph shows us more naively with respect to indices.
The photograph attests to the illusory nature of stability and meaning. During
those bygone eras that favored reality, the designant (désignant), the
designated (referent), indices, and the indicated emerged. In our present
scientific information society, as transfixed by the
real, mental schemata emerge in signs and indices. These schemata intervene in signs and indices,
as we grapple with both reality and the real. However, their activity is more
obvious with indices and the real than with signs and reality. And this explains
why linguists and semiologists have missed the cue as they failed to spot the
swarming plurality of these schemata.