|
LOCAL ANTHROPOGENIES - SEMIOTICS
PHILOSOPHY OF PHOTOGRAPHY
Part one - THE TEXTURE AND STRUCTURE OF THE PHOTOGRAPH
Chapter 7 - THE TRIGGERING OF MENTAL SCHEMATA
The weight of words, the shock of photographs.
PARIS-MATCH
It is necessary to gauge, one last time, to what extent
photography has continuously upset human conduct and behavior. In every
civilization, people have always been immersed in environments where mysteries
were perceived and were part of everyday life. To perceive means, as
phenomenology has long since described it, to be in a place for a duration of
time amongst objects and events disconnected from a background, according to
systems of orientation polarized by two eyes, two ears, two nostrils (on
both sides of the nasal bone, as Bower insists), two arms, two legs, a very
mobile head on an occipital spinal column, to which are added different
successive layers organized according to the degree of cerebral development
(perceptual, logical, semantic schemata), in addition to vast analogical and
digital sign systems that are culturally instituted. Perception as elective and
globalizing: per-capere. What then distinguishes oeuvres that are
considered important, those works that are called masterpieces in the arts and
crafts? The answer is straightforward: it is due to an intensification, a
surcharge of perceptual conditions. From the cave paintings to Cezanne, from
the Andean flutist to the Wagnerian orchestra, one can discern intensified and
surcharged perceptions that secondarily trigger conceptualizations. Through the
curvatures of the trait and the mark, through sonic torsions, through the
gathering in the (pictorial, sculptural, architectural, oratorical, choreographic)
frame-trap, through the coherence of (perceptual, motive, semiotic, and
sometimes indicial) field effects in particular, place is condensed into
ubiquity or multi-presence, while duration is condensed into eternity or Aevum.
Microcosms of the macrocosm. Accordingly, man and his oeuvre were concrete;
they had grown together (con-crescere). The Greek stage, where thousands
of citizens converged in semicircle while focusing on three actors and about
fifteen members of the chorus - all of them embraced by the gaze and hearing -
was one of the most exigent accomplishments of this perceptual pretension. Theatre,
a word derived from the Greek theasthai, means to embrace by the eye
(and the ear) from a fair and equitable distance.
One could say without much exaggeration that the photograph
frustrates nearly every property of perception. Of course, on a photographic
positive one can clearly perceive bright and obscure zones on white paper. In
this respect, the real and reality converge. In the encounter of photons and
halides, the real engenders the black spots while reality intimates that these
are indeed marks or zones. But this is not really what one thinks about when
speaking of photographs and how they are used. The reality that is envisioned
appertains more closely to the possible spectacle that these marks and areas
bring into view. As we have already noted, this spectacle-reality-there,
intensely consumed by the real (by virtue of carrier photons diversely
abstracted and filtered), sidetracks the perceptible and creates a kind of
non-scene through its superficiality of field, its matter-of-fact framing, its
relentless isomorphism and synchronism, its negative-positive alternations, its
ostensible digitality, its informational subcharge and surcharge, and its
monocular and cyclopean capture (while
paintings, although bidimensional, are binocular, which is surely the case with
Cézanne, but also even with Mondrian).
Thus, the most innocent gaze on a photograph creates a
decidedly uncanny situation. On the one hand, there is the viewer who sometimes
walks around in a gallery but who most often is seated and leafs through a
magazine, thus being in a situation of concrete perception. On the other one
hand, there is a sheet of darkened paper that is actually perceived, and which
signals a spectacle that defies almost all perceptual conditions while
displaying space, but by no means a place. Temporally speaking, things are even
stranger. The viewer is well and truly enveloped in a duration, and even in an
actual present, with a consistency characteristic of any present. And
the viewer is confronted with an object whose possible spectacle, for its part,
lacks all consistence of duration. It is even a provocative instance of pure simultaneity
as defined in physics: concomitance, at the speed of light, between the
emission of photons by the spectacle and their impregnation on the film, the
latter datable to a billionth of a second after the passage of the last photon.
In other words, all that concerns the viewer takes place in the present, in the
Bergsonian concrete simultaneity, while all that concerns the photographic
spectacle takes place in four-dimensional space-time, in Einsteinian abstract
simultaneity. And the historical debate between these two illustrious men shows
to what extent the dialogue was really a dialogue of the deaf.
Consequently, this process cannot really occur between
photographic imprints and the body, nor does it occur between signs and
imprints. So, where exactly do things happen? Simply put, everything takes
place between the print's bright and dark areas and our mental schemata.
To clarify this point, and also for historical reasons, it is
absolutely necessary to abandon the technical definition of the sign proffered
by Saussure, and to revisit the term in its common and traditional meaning
which holds that a sign is a complex of signals designating the designated, an event or an object.
Accordingly, one can distinguish six terms that describe this operation of signification.
Signification takes places between the poles of the sign or designated; an
object or event; interpretants, and other signs contrastive with the initial
sign, an addresser (sender) and an addressee, and finally - and this is the
point that interests us here - between the designant (désignant) and the
designated (désigné), a mental scheme. In the world of ancient
artisanship, which was dominated by signs and organized in a relatively stable
reality, the salient points of this operation were, apart from the sender and
addressee, the sign and its designated. We can clearly see that there was a
certain mental schematization at work that was so well wedged between and
aligned with the designated and the designant (désignant) that it
allowed one to speak in the singular using terms such as idea, concept, notion,
or representation. Thus, everything remained within the boundaries of a cosmos,
of a mundus.
Even the smallest of photographs upsets this security. The
photograph does not contain veritable designants (désignants) or signs,
nor does it contain a real designated or referent, and it therefore cannot have
interpretants (the photograph contains very little reality; it is hardly a
universe or microcosm). However, the photographic imprint is often a carrier of
indices, and possibly also indexed indices, and is therefore an extraordinary
trigger of a mental scheme. Or rather, one should say mental schemata.
Because precisely what these indices reveal is that, in their incessant
germination and overlap there are, at every instance, dozens, even hundreds of
mental schemata and not just one single scheme. In other words, this means that
ideas or concepts are semiotic illusions; they are acts of violence imposed by
the desire of reality to capture the ever elusive real. In effect, even in sign
systems, the unity of concepts or ideas cannot be but illusory. When I say
"sugar," whatever may be circulating between the sign and object is by no means
a simple thought but a crossroads where a host of notions may be activated:
substance, matter, sweet, powdery, in pieces, crystalline, fondant, sickening,
pleasant, bad for diabetes, carbon, sugar bread. In common discourse, speakers
incessantly tinker with thousands of mental schemata that spiral and come to
fruition, where metaphors and metonymies are not mere stylistic figures.
Instead, they must be seen as the fundamental functioning. That is precisely
what artificial intelligence has made apparent. To be able to use the
words "arc" or "to walk," artificial intelligence demands that we define them
and that we provide their concepts or ideas. Thus we get underway, believing
that a few well-chosen semantic traits would suffice. But three pages of
semantic traits will still not allow any A.I. to understand or to imagine what
we mean with the phrase "The triumphal arch tilts without threatening to
topple," or, more decisively in "Mark walks with difficulty," or simply "Mark
is walking." The designants (désignants) "arch" and "walk" attain their
designated only through multitudes of mental schemata, and this works
analogically rather than digitally (which is the only way of managing this
worrying plural). What artificial intelligence forces us to acknowledge in the
domain of signs, the photograph shows us more naively with respect to indices.
The photograph attests to the illusory nature of stability and meaning. During
those bygone eras that favored reality, the designant (désignant), the
designated (referent), indices, and the indicated emerged. In our present
scientific information society, as transfixed by the
real, mental schemata emerge in signs and indices. These schemata intervene in signs and indices,
as we grapple with both reality and the real. However, their activity is more
obvious with indices and the real than with signs and reality. And this explains
why linguists and semiologists have missed the cue as they failed to spot the
swarming plurality of these schemata.
|
Lartigue, Musée
Jacquemart-André
|
Surely it is this prodigious
triggering of mental schemata one has in mind when referring, rather joyfully,
to the fantastic in photography. As is repeatedly pointed out in this
respect, photography only marginally satisfies the imaginary as it
deceives perception and designation: one imagines within or in front
of a painting, architecture or a text. By contrast, the photograph does not
have a within, nor does it even have a threshold. The fantastic added a new and
different experience to the imaginary of the past. With Hoffmann, it will
explore the "supernatural," which is not simply the intensification of our
duration and place as was customary in ancient narratives. By the end of the 19th
century, stories will take great pleasure in exploring the more inhuman
aspects of science. The encounter of photography with the real, and therefore
also with science and science fiction, is linked to the fantastic, and as such
it is also connected to surrealism in so far as it is associated with our
understanding of the fantastic. Being such an imposing activator of
ever-spiraling mental schemata, the photograph is closer to the dream
than to the imaginary. And that is why similitudes and contiguities - the stuff
dreams are made of - draw together the mechanisms Freud spotted in his Interpretation
of Dreams, namely condensations (Verdichtung) and slippages
(Verschiebung). These are more indicial and semiotic than metaphors and
metonymies.
All this allows us to focus on common reactions to photography.
One usually chatters around a photograph, when passing the family album around
for instance, in order to simultaneously dispel the panic of the real lurking
underneath and in order to animate a feeble reality. The reading of
photographic captions in magazines ensures that with less exertion the same
informative, animating and apotropaic functions will be fulfilled. But the most
common attitude is leafing through. For every captioned or commented
photograph, there are dozens that are leafed through. Presently, the
overwhelming majority of socially cycled and recycled photographs corresponds
to the criterion not of frontal but of lateral perception, no matter
whether the photographs are on the wall or on the page. It is during their
perusal that photographs (the plural has its importance) trigger off in the
most straightforward and most extensive manner all mental schemata in all
directions through the immediate activation of the eye-brain nexus, thereby
bracketing the other parts of the body. The layout is the staging of
this texture and structure. Nonetheless, sometimes photographs are viewed
attentively without any ulterior motive, and not because one might uncover
clues, as detectives would do, or to discover facial or bodily expressions, as
a lover might do. What do photographs provoke? Interpretations? As
appears from the previous paragraphs, the photograph usually escapes
interpretation and decoding, at least if these are understood as the
progressive lifting of the veil and as semiotic enclosure. In this respect,
Freud is as ill-suited to the task as is Hegel. Viewed as such, the photograph fascinates
us, a bit like a serpent might. The fascinating serpent transfixes us through
its movement from back to front (the intervals of the negative of the
negative), and left to right (the lateral overlap of indices). The serpent is
not actually perceived by the one who is fascinated and stunned by it. The
serpent thus establishes a non-space and non-duration, outside of the
imaginary. But the simile, as with all the others that may apply to
photography, once again breaks down for the same reason. The snake reveals a
depth; it is profundity - its mouth, its gaping stomach: the serpent is depths
itself. And must we yet again repeat that the photograph is infinite
superficiality, that which cannot snatch us up?
Therefore the photograph is both dangerous and reassuring at
the same time. It is the most mentally fascinating thing there is. Leonardo da
Vinci held that paintings were a mental thing, una cosa mentale. But in
fact, it is precisely the photograph that is the mental thing. However,
this does contradict da Vinci. All his paintings, and his fascinating xn
particular, share the most photographic of characteristics, except
superficiality ("Leonardo da Vinci, deep and dark mirror", as Baudelaire
put it). In any case, the "fascinating" adjective has become all the rage
today, and the multiplication of objects and photographic shots is surely no
coincidence.
The photograph, while blurring the pertinent terms of
signification, and activating mental schemata, the latter concerning indices
rather than signs, renders the position of the addressee equally floating, a
position more emphatically referred to in ancient oeuvres, texts or drawings,
even if they only had posthumous aspirations or just spoke to the happy few.
Undoubtedly there are fans of Marilyn or Elvis who think that the poster of
their idol was personally intended for them. However, generally speaking, the
viewer of a photograph does not really feel interpelated, but all the more
impersonally connected to a process that exceeds him. What affects him is not
his entire body or the singularity of sign systems, but precisely his mental
schemata, that is to say, that which is more general, more intangible and the
least individual. We have already spoken at length of the viewer's indifference
to photographs, and his straightforward interest ("how interesting" is
heard even more frequently than "how fascinating"). We attributed this a-pathy
(non-affection in the stoic sense) to habit, which is true. However, the
photograph, like volcano eruptions, tidal waves, or major droughts creates a
more philosophical and radical indifference because of its very texture and
structure, which are closer to the impassive real than to impassioned reality,
provided of course one can agree that understood in this sense, the real is
both impassive and overwhelming.
In Vendredi, ou, Les limbes du Pacifique, Michel
Tournier imagines the situation of a man living alone for years on a deserted
island, and who, instead of maintaining a sense of reality through the use of
signs and social rituals, as Robinson did before him, begins to perceive the trees,
hills, and caverns for what they are in themselves, without much recourse to
referentiality. In order to designate this symbiosis of man and his
environment, the author uses the term phantasm. The
word eloquently recalls the co-incidence (the falling-within-together between
subject and object), the a-mediation (non-mediation, non-dialectic), the
fascination and the imperative coercion (performative) of the phantasm
as defined by psychoanalysis. It also hints at how reality might wither in the
face of the real, or the event in the face of eventuality, or causality in the
face of the black box, or the concept-idea in the face of mental schemata. It
cannot be denied that, even only viewed socially and sociologically, that is to
say in the least photographic way possible, the most familiar or sophisticated
photographs never stop producing, in our eye-brain nexus, something like a
phantasmatization. It is not in Plato's idealistic cavern that one will
understand photography. We need to reach Friday's Pacific island.
|
Suda, c. 1967, Printletter.
|
|
|